Is God a Mathematician
Is God a Mathematician
Is God a Mathematician
by Mario Livio
“The universe appears to have been designed by a pure mathematician.”
– James Jeans (1877-1946), British physicist
“God created the natural numbers, all else is the work of man.”
– Leopold Kronecker (1823-91), German mathematician
“When physicists wander through nature’s labyrinth, they light their way by
mathematics – the tools they use and develop, the models they construct, and the
explanations they conjure are all mathematical in nature.” – Mario Livio
Beginning as far as we know with the Greek philosopher & mathematician Pythagoras
(ca570-ca490 BCE) of Samos & his disciples, the Pythagoreans – “generally credited
with the discovery that dividing a string by simple consecutive integers produces
harmonious and consonant intervals … the mathematical ratios that underlie the harmony
of the musical scale” & “among the first to maintain that the Earth was spherical in form
… also probably the first to state that the planets, the Sun, and the Moon have an
independent motion of their own from west to east, in a direction opposite to the daily
(apparent) rotation of the sphere of the fixed stars” – “the forefathers of the search for
cosmic order” & “the founders of pure mathematics,” arose the passionate belief that
“mathematics was real, immutable, omnipresent, and more sublime than anything that
could conceivably emerge from the feeble human mind.” Promulgated by Plato (429-347
BCE) as belonging “to abstract objects that dwell in an ideal world that is the home of
true forms and perfections” from which “we gain absolutely certain and objective
knowledge” & first formalized (documenting the tradition of the Pythagoreans) by the
“Father of Geometry” Euclid (ca325-ca270 BCE), mathematics “becomes closely
associated with the divine” for centuries afterward, enthralling its adherents with a
conviction in the cosmic connection of its “unreasonable effectiveness.” From
Archimedes (287-212 BCE) – “The perception of mathematics being the language of the
universe, and therefore the concept of God as a mathematician, was born in Archimedes’
work” – to Galileo (1564-1642) – who “showed that observational data become
meaningful descriptions of reality only when embedded in an appropriate mathematical
theory” – to Descartes (1596-1650) – whose ideas “opened the door for a systematic
mathematization of nearly everything – the very essence of the notion that God is a
mathematician … by establishing the equivalence of two perspectives of mathematics
(algebraic and geometric) previously considered disjoint” – to Newton (1642-1728) – as
Alexander Pope expressed in his couplet: “Nature and Nature’s laws lay hid in night:/
God said, Let Newton be! And all was light” – a world came into view in which “the
boundary between mathematics and the sciences was blurred beyond recognition, almost
to the point of a complete fusion between mathematical insights and large swaths of
exploration.”
“Does mathematics have an existence that is entirely independent of the human
mind?” In his book (2009), Mario Livio addresses these questions: “In other words, are
we merely discovering mathematical verities, just as astronomers discover previously
unknown galaxies? Or, is mathematics nothing but a human invention? If mathematics
indeed exists in some abstract fairyland, what is the relation between this mystical world
and physical reality? How does the human brain, with its known limitations, gain access
to such an immutable world, outside of space and time? On the other hand, if
mathematics is merely a human invention and it has no existence outside our minds, how
can we explain the fact that the invention of so many mathematical truths miraculously
anticipated questions about the cosmos and human life not even posed until many
centuries later?”
Very few scientific subjects today still make use of ideas that can be
three thousand years old…. Even though the formalism needed to prove certain
results might have changed, the mathematical results themselves do not change.
In fact, as mathematician and author Ian Stewart once put it, “There is a word in
mathematics for previous results that are later changed – they are simply called
mistakes.” And such mistakes are judged to be mistakes not because of new
findings, as in the other sciences, but because of a more careful and rigorous
reference to the same old mathematical truths. Does this indeed make
mathematics God’s native tongue?
If you think that understanding whether mathematics was invented or
discovered is not that important, consider how loaded the difference between
“invented” and “discovered” becomes in the question: Was God invented or
discovered? Or even more provocatively: Did God create humans in his own
image, or did humans invent God in their own image?
On the other hand of the argument, linguist George Lakoff & psychologist Rafael
Núñez in their book Where Mathematics Comes From presume: “Mathematics is a
natural part of being human. It arises from our bodies, our brains, our everyday
experiences in the world.” British mathematician Sir Michael Atiyah, also a recipient of
the Fields Medal (1966) & the Abel Prize (2004), countered that “man has created
mathematics by idealizing and abstracting elements of the physical world”: “Any
mathematician must sympathize with Connes. We all feel that the integers, or circles,
really exist in some abstract sense and the Platonic view is extremely seductive. But can
we really defend it?”
Had the universe been one-dimensional or even discrete it is difficult to see how
geometry could have evolved. It might seem with integers we are on firmer
ground, and that counting is really a primordial notion. But let us imagine that
intelligence had resided, not in mankind, but in some vast solitary and isolated
jelly-fish, buried deep in the depths of the Pacific Ocean. It would have no
experience of individual objects, only with the surrounding water. Motion,
temperature and pressure would provide its basic sensory data. In such a pure
continuum the discrete would not arise and there would be nothing to count.
The works of Boole, Frege, Peano, Russell, Whitehead, Gödel, and their modern-
day followers (in particular in areas such as philosophical syntax and semantics,
and in parallel lingustics), have demonstrated that grammar and reasoning are
intimately related to an algebra of symbolic logic. But why then are there more
than 6,500 languages while there is only one mathematics? Actually, all the
different languages have many design features in common. [Very recently, using
patterns of phonemes, Quentin D. Atkinson, a biologist, has demonstrated that all
modern languages may have a single origin in southern Africa at least 50,000
years ago, with the accompanying possibility that human language emerged only
once.]
He then cites the contribution from Sir Michael Atiyah again, “whose views on the nature
of mathematics I have largely adopted.”
If one views the brain in its evolutionary context then the mysterious
success of mathematics in the physical sciences is at least partly explained. The
brain evolved in order to deal with the physical world, so it should not be too
surprising that it has developed a language, mathematics, that is well suited for
the purpose.
Livio continues: “This line of reasoning is very similar to the solutions proposed by the
cognitive scientists. Atiyah also recognizes, however, that this explanation hardly
addresses the thornier parts of the problem – how does mathematics explain the more
esoteric aspects of the physical world. In particular, this explanation leaves the question
of what I called the “passive” effectiveness (mathematical concepts finding applications
long after their invention) entirely open. Atiyah notes: ‘The skeptic can point out that the
struggle for survival only requires us to cope with physical phenomena at the human
scale, yet mathematical theory appears to deal successfully with all scales from the
atomic to the galactic.’ To which his only suggestion is: ‘Perhaps the explanation lies in
the abstract hierarchical nature of mathematics which enables us to move up and down
the world scale with comparative ease.’”
Following up on computer scientist Richard Hamming’s suggested solution,
which Livio says for years he had accepted as a full explanation of Wigner’s enigma,
“that humans select, and continuously improve mathematics, to fit a given situation … an
‘evolution and natural selection’ of mathematical ideas” – in his book Dreams of a Final
Theory, Nobel laureate in physics Steven Weinberg proposes a similar interpretation.
“There is no doubt that such selection and evolution indeed occur,” Livio concurs: “After
sifting through a variety of mathematical formalisms and tools, scientists retian those that
work, and they do not hesitate to upgrade them or change them as better ones become
available. But even if we accept this idea, why are there mathematical theories that can
explain the universe at all?” Further, Livio emphasizes the nontrivial fact that “there is a
sufficiently large number of phenomena that mathematics does elucidate to warrant an
explanation. Moreover, the range of facts and processes that can be interpreted by
mathematics continually widens.”
Even Hamming after offering four explanations for the conundrum in 1980 – the
last of which comes close to Atiyah’s by stating, “Darwin’s evolution would naturally
select for survival those competing forms of life which had the best models of reality in
their minds” – conceded that: “if you pick 4,000 years for the age of science, generally,
then you get an upper bound of 200 generations. Considering the effects of evolution we
are looking for via selection of small chance variations, it does not seem to me that
evolution can explain more than a small part of the unreasonable effectiveness of
mathematics.” At the conclusion of his article, Hamming makes the admission,
concerning his hoped for solution to Wigner’s riddle: “all of the explanations I have
given when added together simply are not enough to explain what I set out to account
for.”
So what is it we’ve discovered or invented? Mathematics, God, the universe
itself? Livio asks: “What is it that guarantees that a mathematical theory should exist at
all? In other words, why is there, for instance, a theory of general relativity? Could it not
be that there is no mathematical theory of gravity?”
The answer is actually simpler than you might think. There are indeed no
guarantees! There exists a multitude of phenomena for which no precise
predictions are possible, even in principle. This category includes, for example, a
variety of dynamic systems that develop chaos, where the tiniest change in the
initial conditions may produce entirely different end results. Phenomena that may
exhibit such behavior include the stock market, the weather pattern above the
Rocky Mountains, a ball bouncing in a roulette wheel, the smoke rising from a
cigarette, and indeed the orbits of the planets in the solar system. This is not to
say that mathematicians have not developed ingenious formalisms that can
address some important aspects of these problems, but no deterministic
predictive theory exists. The entire fields of probability and statistics have been
created precisely to tackle those areas in which one does not have a theory that
yields much more than what has been put in. Similarly, a concept dubbed
computational complexity delineates limits to our ability to solve problems by
practical algorithms, and Gödel’s incompleteness theorems mark certain
limitations of mathematics even within itself.