Frankfurt The Importance of What We Care About PDF
Frankfurt The Importance of What We Care About PDF
Frankfurt The Importance of What We Care About PDF
guides himself in what he does with his life and in his conduct. It is
not to be presumed, of course, that whenever a person's life displays
over a period of time some more or less stable attitudinal or
behavioral disposition, this reflects what the person cares about
during that time. After all, patterns of interest or of response may be
manifestations only of habits or of involuntary regularities of some
other kind; and it is also possible for them to develop merely by
chance. T h e y may be discernible, therefore, even in the lives of
creatures who are incapable of caring about anything.
Caring, insofar as it consists in guiding onesself along a distinctive
course or in a particular manner, presupposes both agency and
self-consciousness. It is a matter of being active in a certain way, and
the activity is essentially a reflexive one. This is not exactly because
the agent, in guiding his own behavior, necessarily does something to
himself. Rather, it is more nearly because he purposefully does
something with himself.
A person who cares about something is, as it were, invested in it.
He identifies himself with what he cares about in the sense that he
makes himself vulnerable to losses and susceptible to benefits
depending upon whether what he cares about is diminished or
enhanced. Thus he concerns himself with what concerns it, giving
particular attention to such things and directing his behavior accord-
ingly. Insofar as the person's life is in whole or in part devoted to
anything, rather than being merely a sequence of events whose
themes and structures he makes no effort to fashion, it is devoted to
this.
A person might stop caring about something because he knew he
could not have it. But he might nonetheless continue to like it and to
want it, and to consider it both desirable and valuable. Thus caring
about something is not to be confused with liking it or with wanting it;
nor is it the same as thinking that what is cared about has value of
some kind, or that it is desirable. It is especially to be noted that these
attitudes and beliefs differ significantly from caring in their temporal
characteristics. The outlook of a person who cares about something is
inherently prospective; that is, he necessarily considers himself as
having a future. On the other hand, it is possible for a creature to
have desires and beliefs without taking any accouunt at all of the fact
that he may continue to exist.
Desires and beliefs can occur in a life which consists merely of a
WHAT WE CARE ABOUT 261
Now moral judgments are also impersonal, and in this respect their
force differs fundamentally from that of volitional necessity. Even
when volitional necessity arises in connection with actions which are
required or forbidden by duty, it does not derive from the person's
moral convictions as such but from the way in which he cares about
certain things. If a mother who is tempted to abandon her child finds
that she simply cannot do that, it is probably not because she knows
(or even because she cares about) her duty. It is more likely because
of how she cares about the child, and about herself as its mother, than
because of any recognition on her part that abandoning the child
would be morally wrong. Consistency therefore does not require her
to suppose that the action which she cannot bring herself to perform
must be found to be similarly impossible by every mother whose
circumstances are similar to hers. 2
In the same way, a person who finds that he cannot bring himself to
compromise an ideal to which he has been dedicated, despite his
anxiety concerning the costs of remaining loyal to it, probably is not
being moved most immediately by objective moral considerations
even if the ideal in question is of a distinctively moral variety.
Suppose that someone's ideal is to be meticulously honest in conduc-
ting his business affairs. Everyone is morally obliged, of course, to be
honest; but it does not follow that anyone has a duty to pursue
honesty as an ideal of his life - i.e., to accord to pursuing it the
preemptive attention and concern which commitment to an ideal
entails. A person's discovery that it is volitionally impossible for him
to neglect one of his ideals is not to be equated, then, with an
acknowledgment on his part of an ethical requirement.
Especially with respect to those we love and with respect to our
ideals, we are liable to be bound by necessities which have less to do
with our adherence to the principles of morality than with integrity or
consistency of a more personal kind. These necessities constrain us
from betraying the things which we care about most and with which,
accordingly, we are most closely identified. In a sense which a strictly
ethical analysis cannot make clear, what they keep us from violating
are not our duties or our obligations but ourselves.
6. The formation of a person's will is most fundamentally a matter
of his coming to care about certain things, and of his coming to care
about some of them more than about others. Although these proces-
ses may not be wholly under his voluntary control, it is nonetheless
WHAT WE CARE ABOUT 269
often possible for him to affect them. For that reason, as well as
because people are generally interested in knowing what to think of
themselves, a person may care about what he cares about. This leads
to questions concerning evaluation and justification.
The fact that what a person cares about is a personal matter does
not entail that anything goes. It may still be possible to distinguish
between things that are worth caring about to one degree or another
and things that are not. Accordingly, it may be useful to inquire into
what makes something worth caring about - that is, what conditions
must be satisfied if something is to be suitable or worthy as an ideal
or as an object of love - and into how a person is to decide, from
among the various things worth caring about, which to care about.
Although people may justifiably care about different things, or care
differently about the same things, this surely does not mean that their
loves and their ideals are entirely unsusceptible to significant criticism
of any sort or that no general analytical principles of discrimination
can be f o u n d ]
People often do not care about certain things which are quite
important to them. T h e y may simply fail to recognise, after all, that
those things have that importance. But if there is something that a
person does care about, then it follows that it is important to him.
This is not because caring somehow involves an infallible judgment
concerning the importance of its object. Rather, it is because caring
about something makes that thing important to the person who cares
about it.
It is necessarily the case, of course, that a person who cares about
a certain thing is not cold-bloodedly indifferent to it. In other words,
what happens to the thing must make a difference to a person who
cares about it, and the difference it makes must itself be important to
him. This naturally does not mean that he cares about it just because
it affects him in important ways. On the contrary, it may well be that
he is susceptible to being affected by it or on account of it only in
virtue of the fact that he cares about it.
This suggests that it is necessarily important to people what they
care about. The fact that a person cares about a certain thing or about
some person, or the fact that he does not care about them, makes an
important difference to him. It means that he is, or that he is not,
susceptible to being affected by various circumstances in ways which
he considers important. Thus the question of what to care about
270 HARRY FRANKFURT
w h o m n o t h i n g is a n t e c e d e n t l y i m p o r t a n t - to l o v e a l t o g e t h e r f r e e l y
and without conditions or restrictions of any kind. In any case, a
c a p a c i t y f o r w h o l l y u n c o n d i t i o n e d l o v e is b y n o m e a n s a n e s s e n t i a l
c o n s t i t u e n t o f o u r finite n a t u r e .
W h a t m a k e s it m o r e s u i t a b l e , t h e n , f o r a p e r s o n to m a k e o n e o b j e c t
r a t h e r t h a n a n o t h e r i m p o r t a n t t o h i m s e l f ? I t s e e m s t h a t it m u s t b e t h e
f a c t t h a t it is possible f o r h i m t o c a r e a b o u t t h e o n e a n d n o t a b o u t t h e
o t h e r , o r to c a r e a b o u t t h e o n e in a w a y w h i c h is m o r e i m p o r t a n t to
h i m t h a n t h e w a y in w h i c h it is p o s s i b l e f o r h i m to c a r e a b o u t t h e
o t h e r . W h e n a p e r s o n m a k e s s o m e t h i n g i m p o r t a n t to h i m s e l f , a c c o r d -
i n g l y , t h e s i t u a t i o n r e s e m b l e s a n i n s t a n c e o f d i v i n e agape at l e a s t in a
c e r t a i n r e s p e c t . T h e p e r s o n d o e s n o t c a r e a b o u t t h e o b j e c t b e c a u s e its
w o r t h i n e s s c o m m a n d s t h a t h e d o so. O n t h e o t h e r h a n d , t h e w o r t h i -
ness of the activity of caring commands that he choose an object
w h i c h h e w i l l b e a b l e to c a r e a b o u t .
Yale University
NOTES