Lecture2 3
Lecture2 3
Utility Functions
(x1, x2) > (y1, y2) if and only if u(x1, x2) > u(y1, y2)
Properties of the utility function
Note that the only important feature of the numbers a utility function
assigns to bundles is that it preserves the ranks.
𝑑ƒ(𝑢)
>0
𝑑𝑢
Monotonic transformations
Proposition: If f (·) is any monotonic transformation, and u(x1, x2) is a
utility function that represents a particular set of preferences, then f
(u(x1, x2)) is another utility function that represent the same preferences.
Proof:
•If u(x1, x2) represents a set of preferences, then by definition u(x1, x2)
> u(y1, y2) iff (x1, x2) > (y1, y2)
• And if f (u) is a monotonic transformation, then (also by definition)
u(x1, x2) > u(y1, y2) iff
f (u(x1, x2)) > f (u(y1, y2))
•Therefore, f (u(x1, x2)) > f (u(y1, y2)) iff
(x1, x2) > (y1, y2).
Thus, f (u) represents the same preferences as u.
Utility and indifference curves
Answer: A utility function will assign the same number to all bundles
that lie on a single indifference curve!
His vision of society was that it should produce “the greatest happiness
for the greatest number”.
But how do we know if personA likes ice cream twice as much as person
B?
More importantly, how can you be sure that you like any bundle twice
as much as any other?
Preview: The reason has to do with the notion of marginal utility; that
is, the additional utility gained from another unit of either good. We’ll
come back to this point later!
What kinds of preferences lead to a
utility function?
One kind of preferences that cannot be represented by a utility function
is intransitive preferences.
A2 Transitivity
For all (x1, x2), (y1, y2) and (z1, z2) in X if (x1, x2) < (y1, y2) and (y1,
y2) < (z1, z2), then (x1, x2) < (z1, z2).
A3 Reflexivity
For all (x1, x2) in X , (x1, x2) < (x1, x2)
The axioms continue
A4 Monotonicity
If (x1, x2) ≥ (y1, y2) and either x1> y1 or x2> y2, then (x1, x2) > (y1, y2)
A5 Strict Convexity
For some weight t between 0 and 1:
(t x1 + (1 − t) y1, t x2 + (1 − t) y2) > (x1, x2) ∼ (y1, y2)
A6 Continuity
If (x1, x2) > (y1, y1) then all points “close to” (x1, x2) > all points “close to” (y1, y2).
No jumps in preferences.
Proposition: For any set of preferences that satisfy A1-A6, there exists a
continuous utility function that represents those preferences.
We won’t be going over the proof. This is just another reason that we imposed
all those restrictions on preferences in Ch. 3.
Constructing a utility function
Indifference
Curves
4
x
2
3
2
x1
If you have a utility function u(x1, x2) and you want to create a graphical
representation, it’s easy to draw indifference curves.
Just find all the bundles (x1, x2) such that u(x1, x2) equals some constant,
k.
Then do it again. This set of numbers, that is, all (x1, x2) such that u(x1,
x2) = k is called a level set.
Drawing indifference curves
Suppose we have a utility function u(x1, x2) = x1x2
𝑘
Each indifference curve is defined by the formula x2=
𝑥1
k=4
k=3
Indifference
Curves
k=2
x
2
k=1
x1
A second example
Now suppose we have another utility function v 𝑥&, 𝑥 ( = 𝑥&( 𝑥 ((
Remember the example comparing Coca-Cola and Pepsi (or red and blue peeps)?
Since all that matters is the total number of sodas (or peeps) we can use a very simple
utility function to represent these preferences:
u(x1,x2) = x1 + x2
How can we be sure that this utility function represents preferences for perfect
substitutes?
Where a and b are positive and measure the “value” of goods 1 and 2
to the consumer.
The slope of the indifference curve is −a/b and indicates the rate at
which a is traded off against b.
Perfect complements
Peanut butter and jelly. In this case, all you care is how many sandwiches
you can make.
This is based on the minimum of the units of peanut butter and the units of
jelly that you have.
u(x1, x2) = min {x1, x2}
Think about it this way: how many sandwiches can you make with 3 units
of peanut butter and 3 units of jelly?
Think about this, if we have more than twice as much peanut butter than jelly, then
we will have some peanut butter left over, so we’ll still only get 1 x sandwiches.
x
2
Indifference
Curves
Then, x2 = k − v (x1)
u(x1, x2) = x1 x2
x
2
x1 x1
Cobb-Douglas preferences
These are basically the simplest of the “well-behaved” preferences we
discussed in chapter 3.
For that reason, we’re going to be using this kind of utility function a
lot.
• These indifference curves will look exactly the same as the Cobb-
Douglas indifference curves!
1 𝑐 𝑑
2. v (u(x1, x2)) = 𝑥$𝑐 , 𝑥2𝑑 𝑐# = 𝑥$𝑐#𝑑 𝑥2
𝑐#𝑑
𝑑
𝑐 𝑐' 𝑑
Then we define a = (so = 1) and we can rewrite:
𝑐'𝑑 𝑐'𝑑
This means we can always use a monotonic transformation to ensure that the
exponents in a Cobb-Douglas utility function sum to 1!
Marginal utility
How does a consumer’s utility as we increase the quantity of good 1
in her bundle?
This shows how utility changes as you change the quantity of good 1,
holding the quantity of good 2 fixed.
Marginal utility
Let’s make this definition a little more precise.
∆𝑈 𝑢 𝑥 1 . ∆ 𝑥 1 ,𝑥2 /𝑢(𝑥 1 ,𝑥 2 )
𝑀𝑈& = = lim ∆𝑥1 → - = 0𝑢(𝑥1,𝑥2 )
∆𝑥1 ∆𝑥1 0𝑥 1
This shows how utility changes as you change the quantity of good 1,
holding the quantity of good 2 fixed.
Marginal utility
We can do the same thing for the marginal utility w.r.t. good 2.
∆𝑈 𝑢 𝑥 1 . 𝑥 2 , .∆𝑥 2 /𝑢(𝑥 1 ,𝑥 2 )
𝑀𝑈( = = lim = 0𝑢(𝑥1,𝑥2 )
∆𝑥2 ∆𝑥 2 →- ∆𝑥2 0𝑥 2
It tells you the rate at which a consumer will trade off good 1 and
good 2 at current consumption levels.
With calculus:
𝜕𝑢(𝑥&, 𝑥( ) 𝜕𝑢(𝑥&, 𝑥( )
𝑑𝑢 = 𝑑𝑥& + 𝑑𝑥(
𝜕𝑥& 𝜕𝑥 (
The first term measures the change in utility as we change x1, and the
second term measures the change in utility as we change x2.
𝑑𝑥 2
Now we can solve for 𝑑𝑥 1
, which is the MRS.
This is just:
Using the chain rule, we can calculate the MRS for v (·):
MRS = - 0𝑣/0𝑥 1
= − 0ƒ ⁄0𝑢 0𝑢 ⁄0𝑥 1 = 0𝑢 ⁄0𝑥 1
0𝑣/0𝑥 2 0ƒ ⁄ 0𝑢0𝑢 ⁄ 0𝑥 2 0𝑢 ⁄ 0𝑥 2
If two utility functions have the same MRS, then they represent the same
preferences.
Cobb-Douglas Preferences
Recall that Cobb-Douglas preferences are of the form:
𝑢 𝑥1, 𝑥2 = 𝑥 𝑐 𝑥 𝑑
& (
𝜕𝑢⁄𝛿𝜕
𝑀𝑅𝑆 = −
𝜕𝑢⁄𝜕𝑥2
𝑐𝑥 𝑐%1 𝑥&𝑑
= − 𝑐 𝑑%1
1
𝑑𝑥 1𝑥 &
= − 𝑐𝑥&
𝑑𝑥 1
Cobb-Douglas Preferences
We can take also compute the MRS by taking the log transformation
of the Cobb-Douglas utility function (assured that this will not alter
the underlying preferences) to get:
v 𝑥1, 𝑥2 = c ln 𝑥& + d ln 𝑥(
𝜕𝑢⁄𝜕𝑥& 𝑎
𝑀𝑅𝑆 = − =−
𝜕𝑢⁄𝜕𝑥( 𝑏
Estimating utility functions
Preferences for commuting may depend on, among other things,
travel time, waiting time, explicit cost, etc...
Suppose:
U 𝑥&, , … , 𝑥𝑛 = 𝛽&𝑥& + ⋯ + 𝛽𝑛 𝑥𝑛
They got the following utility function, which fits their data very
well:
𝜕𝑢⁄𝜕𝑥1
𝑀𝑅𝑆 = 𝑑𝑥2⁄𝑑𝑥1 = −
𝜕𝑢⁄𝜕𝑥2