Critical Thinking
Critical Thinking
Critical Thinking
Kevin Possin
Philosophy Department
Winona State University
2002 Kevin Possin For purposes other than making the purchaser's
back-up, no portion of this etext greater than a paragraph or so may be
reproduced in any form without the written permission of the author.
ISBN: 0-9712355-1-1
Published by
Many people would sooner die than think. In fact, they do.
Bertrand Russell
You can fool too many of the people too much of the time.
James Thurber
. . . all our dignity lies in thought. Let us strive, then, to think well.
Blaise Pascal
TABLE OF CONTENTS
1. Introduction
2. Argument Identification
3. Anatomy of an Argument
26
32
51
6. Acceptability
88
7. Relevance
118
152
222
269
Index
Introduction
1. INTRODUCTION
Why critical thinking?
Everyone agrees that one ought to write well, speak effectively, and know at least
enough math to avoid bouncing checks. Thats why these subjects are the socalled basic skills courses that everyone is required to pass in school. But all
of these skills have a more fundamental skill underlying themthinking.
Composition and speech courses teach you how to express your thoughts more
effectively, but they dont teach you how to decide which thoughts ought to be
expressed. And thats our project hereto learn how to think more effectively
and critically.
Is this project relevant to you and your future career? Well, unless you and your
future are totally devoid of thought, yes! In fact, if youre thinking that you
dont have much need for thinking, youve already proven yourself wrong.
Introduction
If believing all and only whats true is our goal in critical thinking, how do we
reach it? What method should we use to form our beliefs so as to maximize this
goal? This is an especially good question in light of the fact that there is an
Introduction
infinite number of methods for deciding what to believe. For example: Believe
the person with the most money, believe the person who talks the loudest, believe
what the Magic 8 Ball says, or believe whatever I tell you [especially about
where to send those cashiers checks for the rest of your life]. But these methods
of belief formation are going to do a pretty lousy job of achieving our goal of
critical thinking, viz., of getting us the truth and nothing but the truth.
So, whats the best method of belief formation? Its having reasons for what
one believes. And not just any old reasons! They have to be good reasons! So,
believe whatever you have good reasons to believe. And believe false whatever
you have good reasons to believe is false. And, if you have no good reason to
think something is true and you have no good reason to think its false, then
simply dont believe anything about it at alljust withhold belief. Honest
ignorance beats false belief any day!
If critical thinking is the practice of forming beliefs on the basis of only good
reasons, what are these reasons and what makes them good reasons?
The best way I know of to come to grips with this fundamental question is by
rewording it a bit. To have good reasons for ones beliefs is to have good
arguments for them. So the practice of critical thinking is the practice of
identifying, having, and giving good arguments for what one believes. By
looking at the structure and quality of arguments, then, we will get a clear picture
of the structure and quality of critical thinking.
Introduction
Not everyone is going to agree with this list of priorities. Thats because not
everyone agrees on what critical thinking is. In fact, recently peoples views on
what critical thinking is have sort of slipped the leash to the point where just
about any thought process passes for critical thinking, by virtue of being creative
or contemplative or self-reflective or by virtue of just being thinking. This is
most unfortunate, because this has mucked things up more than clarified
themtotally contrary to what critical thinking should be accomplishing. A
drunken stupor might well be creative, contemplative, self-reflective, or
whatever, but its hardly an instance of critical thinking!
Calling something critical thinking doesnt make it so. We always need to
remember: Calling a dogs tail a leg doesnt make it a leg, and the poor dog
that thinks it does lands right on its ass.
Introduction
you just cant keep it all in your head? Well, thats the extent to which well be
studying how to use symbols.
Argument Identification
2. ARGUMENT IDENTIFICATION
If our goal is to be able to identify and give good arguments for our beliefs and
values, we need to be able to identify arguments. And in order to do that, we
first need to know what an argument is. [Just think about ithow could you
identify birds if you didnt know what a bird is?!]
Argument Identification
Argument Identification
Hints:
Argument Identification
Argument indicators
The two essential parts of an argument, the premises and the conclusion, are
often connected by certain terms or phrases. These terms indicate whether
statements are being used as premises or as conclusions. As a result, these
indicators are good indicators of arguments. Heres a list of some of the most
frequently used premise indicators and conclusion indicators. [This list is not
exhaustive, but youll easily be able to extrapolate to new cases after becoming
familiar with these.]
Premise Indicators:
since
because
is implied by
is entailed by
is inferred from
for
given that
follows from
as shown by
as is demonstrated by
for the reason that
on the basis of
on the grounds that
is deduced from
is derived by
Conclusion Indicators:
therefore
hence
thus
so
then
it follows that
implies that
entails that
can be inferred that
for this reason
Argument Identification
accordingly
consequently
proves that
shows that
demonstrates that
one can conclude that
Mere assertions
Now that we are clear on what an argument is, we can begin to look at some of
the other important things people do with languageother speech acts, as they
are called.
People often do not bother to give an argument for what they believe or value;
they rest content simply stating what they believe or value. If their statement is
not obviously true, if instead it is quite controversial, their statement is a mere
assertion.
10
Argument Identification
11
Argument Identification
This view is called relativism. It has become very popular, advocated by many
authors and educators. But its a view that is self-defeating and utterly false.
Heres why.
When someone advocates relativism, they intend their position or statement to
be true. And not just true for them, but simply truetrue for everyone. But
then, if relativism is true for everyone, relativism must be false, since there
would then be at least one statement that is true for everyone, namely the
statement Relativism is true. But thats exactly what relativism says cant
happen!
So if relativism is true, then it would imply that its false. [And, of course, if its
false, then its just plain false.] So, relativism is just plain false!
The only way for the relativist to avoid this is to intend relativism merely as a
matter of their own opinion, applicable only to their own personal opinions. But
then the relativists statement Relativism is true is no more justified than
its denial, and has no relevance to anyone else with the opposite opinion.
Lets explode a couple more renditions of relativism. How about All opinions
are equal? If it were true that all opinions are equal, then the opinion that All
opinions are not equal would be equally true. But if All opinions are not
equal is true, then All opinions are equal must be false. So All opinions are
equal must be false.
How about Everything is just subjective; nothing is objective? Well, if its
true that Everything is just subjective; nothing is objective, then there must be
at least one state of affairs that is objective and not just subjective, namely, that
everything is just subjective and not objective. But then its false that
Everything is just subjective; nothing is objective. The truth of Everything is
just subjective; nothing is objective, would entail its own falsity. So
Everything is just subjective; nothing is objective must be false. [Oooooo, that
blew up real well!]
Ill leave it to you to demolish the remaining versions of relativism on our list.
Have fun showing how these wise-sounding expressions self-refute the instant
theyre proposed:
Everything is just a matter of opinion.
Its all just a matter of taste.
Things are only true for an individual or a culture.
There are no facts.
There are no truths.
Nothing is absolute.
12
Argument Identification
So some claims are not just subjective; they are not mere matters of opinion.
Some claims are objectiveeither objectively true or objectively false. The
problem is to figure out which claims are merely subjective and which claims are
objective.
Indeed, some statements are merely subjective and are thereby merely true for
the individuals expressing them; for example, if I were to say Broccoli tastes
pretty good, and you say Broccoli tastes horrid! Here, there is no objective
fact of the matter regarding broccolis good-tastingness for us to be right or
wrong about. I am basically saying I like the way broccoli tastes, while you
are saying I dont like the way broccoli tastes. In fact, we are not even
disagreeing, since there is nothing for us to disagree about.
On the other hand, if I were to claim Broccoli has mass, while you claimed
Broccoli does not have mass, we would have a disagreement, because there is
something for us to disagree about, namely, it is an objective matter as to
whether or not broccoli has massit either does or it doesnt, and in fact, it does.
Note that whether a statement is merely a subjective matter of taste or an
objective matter is itself an objective matter. Its not just a matter of taste
whether or not something is a mere matter of taste. So, the fact that a claim is
merely subjective (or not) is itself objective. And in light of that, the claim that
an issue is merely subjective, unless its obviously true, will need an argument
to support it. The failure to provide such an argument will mean that the claim
remains a mere assertion, leaving its audience with no reason to think its true.
How do you argue that a matter is subjectivea mere matter of taste? It all
hinges on the following question: Does it make sense to think there is an expert
on the matter? Take our case of two people arguing about the good-tastingness
of broccoli; would it make any sense to think that an expert on the goodtastingness of food could be brought in to shed some light on the issue and help
decide whos right? No! Its just silly to think someones going to get their
Ph.D. in the good-tastingness of food. Theres no such thing as an expert on this,
and its silly to think there could be one. Either you like the taste of something or
you dontend of matterall tastes or opinions on this are equal. Whereas, if
these two were arguing about whether broccoli has mass, it would make
perfectly good sense to seek an experts opinionthe chemists or the physicists
opinion. Or, if the disagreement were about the goodness of broccoli in terms of
its nutritional value or its freshness, one could consult a nutritionist in the first
case and a gardener or grocer in the second.
So now we have a sort of litmus test to use to argue that a matter is either
subjective or objective. Once we have reason to believe that were facing an
objective matter, we then have the task of figuring out what we should believe
and what we should not believe about it. And thats the function of arguments
13
Argument Identification
to help us believe the true claims and refrain from believing the false ones,
since now we surely know that not all assertions are equal.
14
Argument Identification
15
Argument Identification
Something to notice about these cases is that not a single one of them is a
statement. A statement is a declaration, a claim that is either true or false. And
none of the listed sentences is either true or false. Try them. For example, the
question Is the door shut? gets Yes or No, but not True or False, as a
sensible reply.
Pop quiz: Think about the phrase I just used Try them. Is
it a statement?
Arguments and assertions are made of statements, as are two other important
speech acts you should be able to distinguishdescriptions and explanations.
A description is simply a statement or claim that is obviously true in the context
of its use. Heres an example.
Watson and Crick were helped greatly by actually trying to
construct a physical model of DNA. This was a model in the
ordinary sense in which model airplanes and dollhouses are
models. They are all scale models. The big difference between
Watson and Cricks model and more familiar scale models is the
extreme nature of the scale, which, in the case of the DNA
model, was roughly a billion to one. That is, an inch in the
model represented roughly one one-billionth of an inch in an
actual DNA molecule. [Ronald Giere, Understanding Scientific
Reasoning]
When someone is using a statement as a description, no derivative point is
made by means of the statement, i.e., no conclusion is being drawn from it, and
no reason is given to believe the statement, since none is neededwe are simply
willing to take the authors word for it. We are not the least bit inclined to ask,
Now why ought I to believe that?
16
Argument Identification
17
Argument Identification
tell you that my shoulder hurts because I have a bone spur, the pain in my
shoulder is the explanandum and the bone spur is the explanans.
The distinction between explanations and descriptions gets a bit blurry
sometimes. One reason for this is that when one gives an explanation, one is, in
a sense, describing the conditions, events, or states of affairs that bring about
another set of conditions, events, or states of affairs. But in such a context, ones
statement is functioning ultimately as an explanation and not as a mere
description.
Another source of confusion is that we often speak of people explaining how
things are donefor example, when someone explains how to get to the nearest
gas station or how to tie a shoe. But these are better characterized as descriptions
descriptions of how to get to a certain location or state of affairs. The same
goes for explaining how things lookthese are just descriptions. [Our language
is pretty loose with the use of the word explanation, unfortunately.]
18
Argument Identification
Failing to get that result means the end of the heart and its action. [Note: The
hearts pumping action causally explains a thumping sound too, but that is not its
function, since the heart was not selected for because it produces such a sound,
and its failing to produce such a sound (e.g., for the deaf) would not mean the
end of its pumping action.]
19
Argument Identification
20
Argument Identification
Z
X
This would be a great argument for the poles being X ft. tall. It would just be a
basic application of the Pythagorean Theorem. But weird things happen when
you try to warp this into service as an explanation. You mean to tell me that the
cables being Z ft. long and touching the ground Y ft. from the base of the pole
made the pole X ft. tall?! Say Hallelujah, praise the cable!!
No, the explanation of the poles being X ft. tall is going to be something else
entirely: maybe its because Groundskeeper Willie cut it off at that length, or
that its an Acme flagpole, and Acme flagpoles only come in that size.
Whatever, the explanation is going to be something like this.
And take another look at this example:
K is not pregnant, because K is taking birth control pills that are
extremely reliable.
This was used as both an argument and an explanation earlier. But now lets say
the sentence is about meKevin. How well could it work as an explanation
now? It really couldnt. Even assuming that Im consistently taking my
extremely reliable birth control pills every morning, those pills just could not
work as a prevention of my pregnancy. My lack of the proper wetware, so to
speak, is a better candidate for that.
However, could the fact that Im consistently taking my birth control pills every
morning function as an argument for believing that Im not pregnant? Yes, it
couldjust as well as it could function as a reason for believing that Kay isnt
pregnant. If Kay and I are taking the same birth control pills and they are 99.9%
reliable, then they make it 99.9% probable that each of us isnt pregnant. There
21
Argument Identification
is, of course, a much better reason to believe that Im not pregnant, but that
would be a different argument.
I hope these casescases in which an explanation could not work as an
argument and an argument could not work as an explanationhelp you to keep
these two different speech acts separate. Arguments and explanations function
differently, despite the fact that they look so much alike and despite the fact that
the same passage can often function as either.
Heres one last example, to help you distinguish between an argument and an
explanationthe gas gauge. The position of the gauges needle, e.g., its being
on E, works well as a reason or argument for thinking that the tank is empty.
The needles being on E does not, however, explain the tanks being empty.
Just the reversethe tanks being empty explains why the needles on E.
22
Argument Identification
23
Argument Identification
the other hand [no pun intended], can use the sentence Oh, thats real good! at
one time to compliment someone and at another time to level a sarcastic insult.
We can even use it to mean I have the State secrets on me, lets meet at the
usual rendezvous for their delivery. We can use the phrase to mean an infinite
number of different things.
Does this mean that words mean whatever we take them to mean? Well, Yes,
repeat No! We indeed are the ones in charge of assigning meanings to words
and sentences; we can use a sentence to mean one thing as opposed to another.
But, if we ever want to use language successfully as a form of communication,
we cant be glib and anarchistic about it. If we wish to communicate our
thoughts by means of linguistic symbols, we need our audience to be familiar
with the symbols we use and to know that we mean one thing as opposed to
another by those symbols, or else our audience simply will not understand what
were expressing.
So, its possible to use a sentence in an infinite number of ways to mean an
infinite number of things; just dont expect to get your point across as you
exercise this possibility.
You can use a screwdriver as a screwdriver or as a can opener or as a
paperweight, but dont try to make it function as a wedding ring and expect to be
taken seriously.
So, as you read and listen to others and try to figure out what they are saying and
which speech acts they are performing, dont so much wonder what they could
mean; rather, ask what in all probability do they mean, given that they
arent insane and wish to communicate with the average audience? This
is exactly what to keep in mind as you practice Argument Identification, either
in the CT software or in daily discourse.
24
Argument Identification
25
Anatomy of an Argument
3. ANATOMY OF AN ARGUMENT
Ive been milking the analogy between critical thinking and field biology pretty
hard: We first learn the features that distinguish the species of speech acts and
then learn to identify them in the field. Well, Im going to milk this analogy a
bit more.
To fully understand a particular organism, what makes it tick and all, you have to
dissect it. Youve got to look inside, to see its parts and how theyre connected.
Likewise with arguments. To fully understand how they are functioning so as to
provide reasons for believing their conclusions, you have to dissect them into
their component premises and conclusions. This is also the only way to tell the
healthy, well-functioning members of the species from the sickly ones. And that,
remember, is our projectto study what makes a good argument a good
argument.
26
Anatomy of an Argument
27
Anatomy of an Argument
28
Anatomy of an Argument
P1*
P1
P2*
P2
C1/P3
P4
C2/P5
C3
For those of you who are more imagistically inclined, with respect to how you
think about things, heres another way to map out the taxonomy of an argument.
I happen to like this way of representing arguments, because I tend to think better
using images. Others find it rather unhelpfuljust a bunch of goofy circles and
29
Anatomy of an Argument
arrows. The bottom line is this: Use whichever means works best for you to
understand the anatomy and dynamics of arguments.
30
Anatomy of an Argument
31
32
33
Lets begin a closer study of these two cogency conditions by looking at one very
important way of meeting the conduit condition.
Logical entailment
The strongest way an argument can meet the conduit requirement for cogency is
called logical entailment. There are many names for this relation, so let me just
list the most popular ones:
The premises logically entail the conclusion.
The premises logically imply the conclusion.
The premises deductively imply the conclusion.
The premises deductively entail the conclusion.
The conclusion follows logically from the premises.
The conclusion follows deductively from the premises.
The conclusion follows validly from the premises.
There are two ways of describing the tight connection between premises and
conclusion in logical entailment:
For now, lets focus on this second way of capturing the strong relation of logical
entailment.
Heavy-duty impossibility
When premises logically imply their conclusion, its logically impossible for the
conclusion to be false while the premises are true. Its not just technically
impossible for the conclusion to be false while the premises are true. And its not
just physically impossible for the conclusion to be false while the premises are
true. Its logically impossible for the conclusion to be false while the premises
are true.
Heres what I mean. You probably thought that when something is impossible,
that just means it cant happen. Well, not quite; because impossibility comes in
different strengths. For example, its impossible for a laptop computer to process
at 5 gigaflops [5 billion floating-point operations per second]. But this is only a
technical impossibility. The desktop Mac G4 is there already, and, as soon as a
34
few more technical limitations are surmounted, the feat will be accomplished by
a laptop tooand probably not long after Im done keying this sentence in.
Technical impossibility is the weakest; its only a function of a lack of enabling
conditions.
Its quite a different matter, however, that its impossible for my laptop computer
to hover six feet off the ground unassisted. This is not just due to a limitation of
conditions; its not just due to technical shortcomings. No, if a laptop were to do
this, it would be breaking a law of nature. A law of physics called gravitation
makes it physically impossible for laptops to do this. If the laws of physics were
differentfor example, if the law of gravitation were no longer the caseit
would be possible; but not until then.
But there is even a s t r o n g e r form of impossibility; and thats logical
impossibility. Its the impossibility of, e.g., ever having a square circle or a
married bachelor. These two things could just never happen, even if you had
complete run of the laws of nature to form them however you wanted to make
things. For example, we could make a much brighter universe if we played
God and changed the laws of optics from inverse-squared laws to simple
inverse-proportionality laws. [Or we could do a little mood-lighting and
change the laws of optics to an inverse-cubed relation of brightness to distance.]
But no matter how we might tinker with the laws of physics in this manner [and
of course we cant!], we could never, ever produce a squared circle or a married
bachelor. They are logical impossibilities.
A square circle and a married bachelor are contradictions. A bachelor is an
unmarried male. And so a married bachelor would have to be married and
unmarried at the same time. This cant be, no matter what tinkering with the
laws of nature might permit. God couldnt even create a married bachelor, and
Gods supposed to be all powerful. My point here is that logical impossibility is
the strongest of all impossibilitiesits so impossible that even God couldnt do
it. Wow; thats pretty impossible!
35
reasonable. You hear psychologists call a test valid, by which they mean that the
test actually measures the desired phenomenon.
But we will be using valid in the more technical sense stated in bold type
above; this is what validity is from the point of view of logic. This will cut down
on potential confusions as we talk about the cogency requirements of arguments,
I promise.
36
37
list of cogency conditions we will be studying and implementing for the rest of
this project.
Relevance of premises:
I first ran across this way of unpacking the cogency conditions in Trudy Goviers
A Practical Study of Argument. Its a wonderful text (the second best I know of
;-), with a helpful way of remembering the ingredients for a cogent argument:
ARG is the acronym for our three conditionsacceptability, relevance, and
groundednessand its also the first three letters of the word argument. [Admittedly, groundedness is a bit clumsy, so I considered calling it the support
condition, until it came time to do the acronym.]
We will soon take a close look at the acceptability condition, in Chapter 6,
studying what having acceptable premises is all about. We will also examine
some of the most popular ways of meeting the acceptability condition and some
of the most popular ways of failing to meet it.
In a similar fashion, the new relevance condition will be studied in depth later,
in Chapter 7. But for now, a basic understanding of the relevance of premises
can be gained from the following example.
Say that I conclude that chickadees love sunflower seeds, on the basis of my
seeing a single chickadee eat a single sunflower seed. Is my reason relevant to
my universal conclusion? Well, yes; its at least some evidence. Its at least
more evidence than I had before I witnessed any chickadee at all eat a sunflower
seed. Admittedly, my reason would be a very weak one; but its at least relevant.
In order to meet the groundedness condition for cogency, however, I would
need enough evidence to adequately support my universal conclusion about
38
chickadees loving sunflower seeds. I would need evidence that would make it at
least probable that all chickadees love sunflower seeds.
Lets begin taking a more detailed view of our ARG conditions by zooming in on
this groundedness condition a bit.
Deductive arguments
Inductive arguments
We have already briefly discussed the first way for premises to ground their
conclusions, viz., by deductively entailing those conclusions. In Chapters 8-9,
we will study deductive arguments in detail and learn a number of ways to assess
their validity.
In future chapters, Ill discuss how to assess various forms of inductive argumentsso please be on the lookout for the upgrade of this etext.
At this time, however, lets just get clear on what the difference is between the
two types of arguments, since it has been a major source of confusion for many,
many people.
39
40
So inductive arguments are informative, but have only imperfect truth preservation.
As with all things in life, it seems, there is a trade-off. This time it is between
informativeness and truth preservation. Inductive arguments leak when true
premises are thrown into their hopper. At most they make their conclusions
probably true, but never true with logical certainty.
This is why science can use only inductive arguments as it tells us about the
world on the basis of experiential evidence. As it informs us about how the
world is or predicts how the world will be, it does so on the basis of recorded
observations. But the degree to which it can so inform us is the degree to which
it cannot be certain in its conclusions. If certainty is our goal, we must lower our
expectations and settle for only explicitly repeating claims we already implicitly
granted in our premises.
41
42
The old mistaken distinction gets things accidentally correct once and a while,
but it often gets things just plain wrong. Here are some examples to illustrate
this:
I own a vehicle with Minnesota license number XXX123.
The vehicle with Minnesota license number XXX123 is a Toyota.
I own a Toyota.
We know full well that this is a deductive argument. But if we were to classify it
on the basis of the popular account, what would it be? It argues from specific
premises about a particular vehicle and license number, to a specific conclusion
about that same vehicle. So it couldnt be either deductive or inductiveits
schminductive?!
The popular account cant handle this very common type of argument. But our
analysis had no problem figuring out what type of argument it is. Try this one:
Many overhead projectors that Ive dropped have broken.
The next overhead projector I drop will break.
This is obviously an inductive argument. But what would the popular account do
with it? It argues from a more general premise to a specific conclusion; so, the
popular account would mistakenly classify this as a deductive argument.
Check this out: Even one of the greatest critical thinkers of all
time, Sherlock Holmes, was totally screwed up about the
deductiveinductive distinction. When he thought he was
deducing conclusions on the basis of his observations, he was
in fact making inductive inferences. Have a lookgo to the
website www.concordance.com and do a search on Sherlock
Holmes, and then do a couple of searches on deduce and
43
Validity revisited
Ive discussed how validity is a very technical notion for us as we study critical
thinking. From our point of view of logic, remember, validity is simply a matter
of it being logically impossible for the premises to be true while the conclusion is
false.
To really highlight how technical and fine-grained our working concept of
validity is, lets critically examine the following claim from Trudy Govier, in A
Practical Study of Argument:
Deductive entailment is so tidy and complete a connection that
when we have it there is no need to consider separately the
relevance of premises and the issue of whether they provide
good grounds for the conclusion.
Goviers point is that when an argument meets the groundedness condition for
cogency, we can automatically check off the relevance condition as also having
been met. Well, that might normally be true, but its not always the case. And
by taking a look at some of those exceptions, we will get an even more robust
understanding of what validity is and an even better idea of what the relevance
condition is all about.
Bill Clinton was president.
Bill Clinton was not president.
This is a critical thinking etext.
Is this argument valid? Its squirrelly; thats for sure. But is it valid?
The question to ask, of course, is whether its logically impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false at the same time. And the answer is
Yes. Its impossible for the premises to be true while the conclusion is false,
because its simply impossible for the premises to be trueits impossible for
Clinton both to have been president and not to have been president. That would
be a contradiction, and contradictions cant be true. Look at it this way: If its
simply impossible for me to be in Chicago right now, then its surely also
impossible for me to be in Chicago right now having a good time. See?
So the argument is valid. And, by being valid, it meets the groundedness condition [if only by getting by on a technicality!]. Does it meet the relevance
condition? Do the premises provide one with even the weakest reason to believe
44
the conclusion? The answer is No. Neither the Clinton presidency nor its
termination provided any reason whatsoever to believe that this is a critical
thinking etext.
So we see already that meeting the groundedness condition for cogency does not
guarantee that one has met the relevance condition.
45
cannot validly infer that the relevance condition is met simply on the basis of an
arguments being valid.
Another pop quiz: Ill leave the answers and their explanations
for you to discover:
Bill Clinton was president.
Bill Clinton was president.
Is this argument valid?
Are the premises relevant?
Is the argument sound?
Relevance of premises:
46
By this time it must be striking you that Im on a crusade about keeping the three
ARG conditions distinct. Before you begin chalking me up as an obsessivecompulsive, let me lay out my reasons.
Say your car is running a bit rough and you take it into the shop; what would you
think if all the mechanic could say about your car is, It dont run so good? You
knew that! This clown calls themself a mechanic, and thats all they can offer by
way of a diagnosis?!
You want a mechanic who knows why its not running. You want someone who
can distinguish the various systems of the car and knows what makes them wellfunctioning and what causes their malfunctioning; so he or she can fix the broken
parts and leave the good parts alone.
And so it is with arguments. We want to be able to say more than just, That
dont sound so good, when were confronted with a poor argument. We want to
be able to spot exactly where the argument is going right and where its going
wrong; so that when arguments go haywire, we can fix what needs fixing and
only what needs fixing.
And thats why we are making such a big deal about distinguishing the ARG
conditions. And thats why our whole project here, in our goal of becoming good
critical thinkers, is to become proficient at applying the ARG conditions to
argumentswhether they be inductive or deductive arguments; whether they be
others or our own.
Dont be lulled into thinking that an argument is cogent simply because you
happen to agree with its conclusion. Remember: There are plenty of terrible
arguments for conclusions that happen to be accidentally true. So when someone
offers you a noncogent argument for your conclusion, you would do well to say,
Thanks, but no thanks. Many people cant understand how you could accept
their conclusion but object to their argument; but thats just their problemtheir
47
48
But this just removes one reason for believing C is true. This is not the same as
providing a reason for believing C is false. This would require giving an
argument for not C.
Lacking a reason to think that C is true does not mean that one has a reason for
thinking C is false.
Furthermore, providing such a reason for thinking C is false, viz., giving a n
argument for not C, is not the same as providing a reason for believing some
other alternative conclusion C* is true. This would require giving a different
argument for C*.
We must always keep the following distinct:
A criticism of an argument for C
An argument against C
An argument for C*
We must always remember that:
A criticism of an argument for C is not an argument against C.
An argument against C is not an argument for C*.
49
Whats next?
This ends our first look at the cogency conditions for arguments. In the next
chapter, we will look at the most fundamental material of argumentation and
critical reasoninglanguage. Coming up: The use and abuse of language in
critical thinking.
50
51
another sense they are not disagreeing at all. In a sense, they are just talking two
different languages and, as a result, might as well be on different ends of the
planet. The only solution to their problem is to call a linguistic time-out from
their debate and come to some kind of agreement on what constitutes a safe
research practice.
Both Jean and Parry agree that its physically possible for genetic research to
result in an organism that causes widespread environmental damage. For Parry,
however, this means that the research is unsafe. Parry is using a different
definition or meaning of what it is to be safe than Jean is using. For Parry, safe
means the physical impossibility of damage. That is not what Jean means by the
word safe. For Jean, safe means being within normal and tolerated risks of
damage. So for Jean, an activity would have to significantly increase the chances
of harm over the normal base rate in order to qualify as being unsafe.
It appears that Jean is more in tune with what we standardly mean by a safe
activity, and Parry is quite out of step with our ordinary understanding. Look at
it this way: If Parry were right about what being unsafe is all about, then
everything we do is unsafe, and we would have to call ourselves a constant
danger to others. As you meet a friend on the street you wave to them; but in so
doing, there is a chance that your watch band could break, flinging your watch
into their face, and taking their eye out! Its physically possible! Does that make
you a walking hazard to others? Does that mean we should prohibit you from
waving to your friends, at least when you have your watch on? Of course not!
No, by simply sharing the planet with others, we are forced to accept some risks
in exchange for the benefits of doing social actions. Its called having a life.
Driving a car while being stone sober and attentive still poses the risk of mowing
a pedestrian downhe was right in the window post and he dashed out on the
road and you didnt see him in time. Thats a tragic accident; its not reckless
driving. But if you do two six-packs and get one eye looken at the other and
then go cruising around, thats unsafe driving. Driving while drunk significantly
increases the probabilities of injuring others over the base rate of sober, attentive
driving.
So before Jean and Parry started their exchange of arguments, they should have
called a little linguistic convention, to come to some agreement about what they
both mean by the words safe and unsafe.
And, if they wanted their debate to be understood and used by others, they
should also agree to use those words in the same way the general public does, or
they will still be talking past everyone else.
52
Definitions
The episode with Jean and Parry illustrates the importance of clearly and
explicitly defining ones terms. Later, we will see other benefits of doing this.
Right now, however, lets address the fundamental question of what a definition
is.
53
So far we have:
apples
crustat least one
Is that enough? Not really. This would mean that if someone rolled out a crust
and placed an apple or two on top of it, it would be an apple pie. And it just
isnt; its just a crust with a couple of apples laying on it. An apple pie must be
put together in the right way. The apples must be sliced up a bit. To capture this
in our definition, lets just say Some assembly required. [This too would need
further elaboration, but I think we have a pretty good idea of what were referring
to here.]
Lets round up our ingredients and see if theyre enough:
apples
crustat least one
proper assembly
This still falls short, because you could roll out a crust, slice some apples on it,
fold one half over the other, pinch the edges, and all youd get is an apple
turnover, not an apple pie. Shape is important here. Its got to be, well, pieshaped. But whats that? Well, its that the crust is shaped or formed in what
we call a pie plate or baking tin. Lets call this ingredient pieshaped and add it
to our list. [Well see in a bit, whats wrong with this, but lets move on for
now.]
apples
crustat least one
proper assembly
pieshaped
Will this do the job? If we get all these ingredients together, do we automatically
have an apple pie, or do we need some more ingredients?
Do we need to bake it? Well, let me tell you a little story. When I was a kid, we
had an apple tree. My job was to pick the apples and clean, peel, and slice them.
In the mean time, my mom made crusts, rolling them out, laying them in tins, and
passing them to me. I would then fill them with apple slices, a little sugar, and
more cinnamon than she liked, and pass them back to her. Shed then lay the top
crusts on and slide them back to me. Id press the crusts edges together with a
fork, trimming off the excess, and wrap them in tin foil and put them in the
freezer by the dozens for winter. What was I putting in the freezer? If we say
that, by definition, apple pies need to be baked, then I cant have been putting
54
apple pies in the freezerthey must have been schmapple pies. But we know
full well that they were apple pies; so baking should not be added to our list.
How about sugar? Can we get by without it? Well, yes. Youd have an apple
pie so tart it would grab your throat like a pit bull, but it would still be very sour
apple pie. How about cinnamon? Do we need it? Again, we can get by without
it. Our definition guarantees only an apple pie when were done, not necessarily
a tasty one.
So it looks as if weve finished our definition.
Weve discovered all the ingredients that an apple pie must have in order to be
an apple pie. These are called the necessary conditions.
Weve also discovered all the necessary conditions which when rounded up
automatically guarantee us an apple pie. These are called the jointly sufficient
conditions.
So, the primary goal of a definition is to provide the necessary and jointly
sufficient conditions for the proper use of a term.
Conceptual analysis
The goofy little example we just did, clarifying the definition of apple pie, was
a good example of whats called conceptual analysis.
Use this method of conceptual analysis to discover and refine any definition:
Eventually gather all the necessary features that will make for
the thing being defined. These features are jointly sufficient
conditions.
55
56
57
58
Even more to think about: If there are persons who are not
human, are there humans that are not persons? And do they have
rights?
The dictionary
Youve been told since childhood that the best [or only] source of definitions is
the dictionary. Well, after analyzing what a definition is, we can now see that
thats not necessarily true.
The dictionary should have the first word on what the definition of a word
is, but not necessarily the last word.
So far weve discussed two goals of a definition:
1) To detail the meaning of a word as it is commonly
intended or used by ones linguistic community.
2) To detail the necessary and sufficient conditions for being
the thing defined.
Quite often, these goals do not coincide. Quite often, the general linguistic
communitys understanding of the complete set of necessary and sufficient
conditions for the appropriate application of a term is rather impoverished or in
error. So, since the primary function of the dictionary is to accurately reflect how
the linguistic community uses terms, its not surprising that it will frequently
stray from accurately detailing the actual analyses of things.
59
60
Another way in which a definition can fail to increase ones understanding of the
definiendum is when the definiens uses more esoteric terms or concepts than the
definiendum was in the first place. Remember how irritating it was to look up a
word only to have to look up another word that was used in the definition?
The moral of this story : Use more primitive and understandable terms or
concepts in the definition.
Of course, sometimes this virtue of a good definition is incompatible with
another virtue. Sometimes, for example, increasing the accuracy of a definition
entails using less primitive concepts, with the resultant definition being less
intelligible to the layperson than was the original term. You have to make a
judgment call at that point, between losing a bit of your accuracy or losing a
portion of your audience.
61
If I tell you that Ann said that there are no good restaurants in Winona, am I
claiming that there are no good restaurants in Winona? No, and anyone ascribing
me with that claim would be misrepresenting me and what I said. Not much
hangs in the balance in this instance; but in other cases, it might be different.
If I tell you that Bob said youre an idiot, am I calling you an idiot? No, but if
you ignore the use-mention distinction, you might mistakenly think that I just
insulted you by calling you an idiot, when I didnt at all. And this is how
feelings can get hurt and accusations begin to fly.
This especially happened to a friend of mine who was teaching a writing seminar
at a major corporation. The topic was the use of informal language in business
correspondence, and one participant asked if there were ever an occasion in
which the word nigger could be used. After the shock of the question wore off,
my friend said that it would never, never, ever be appropriate or permissible to
use that expression. She was later accused by the corporations Human
Resources Department of using racist language in her seminar. This was a most
unfortunate misrepresentation of herher attempt to battle against racism was
treated as an expression of it.
Indeed, here is a case in which a word has such a history that it may be
psychologically impossible for us to maintain the use-mention distinction. This
is why its often best to only indirectly mention those offensive cases when we
must, e.g., by means of abbreviations, as with the N word.
62
Conclusions by definition
We have been discussing definitions and the importance of sharing the same
definitions in order to communicate with others and understand their claims and
their arguments. Lets now examine a more specific use of definitions.
We often say that a statement is true by definition. For example, if Bob is a
bachelor, then we could say that Bob is unmarried, by definition. Arguments in
which the conclusion follows by definition are all valid deductive arguments.
Their conclusions will be uninformative, in the same sense that all deductively
valid arguments are, and often rather obviously so, as with the case about Bob.
The conclusion is just unpacking one of the necessary conditions making up the
definition.
And this is why, in this kind of argument, all the real work is being done by the
definition given in the premise. But, garbage in might well get you garbage
out, as we see in the following argument.
The American Heritage Dictionary defines murder as The
unlawful killing of one human being by another, esp. with malice
aforethought. And State executions are neither unlawful nor are
they done with malice aforethought. Therefore, the death
penalty is not murder.
This illustrates the danger of blithely appealing to the dictionary as a source of
argumentation. Remember, the dictionary may have the first word, but never the
last; here the dictionary definition is too narrow, by requiring that the murder be
against the law. Certainly, a legalized case of murder is not a contradictionthe
Holocaust illustrates this.
There is no substitute for thorough conceptual analysis. And then, once a
clear and well-tested analysis or definition is determined, conclusions can be
more confidently drawn from it.
This is exactly the project in crucial ethical debates about the moral
permissibility of abortion or of euthanasia. Lives literally hang in the balance
depending on determining the correct analysis or definition of a person or of
death. We must first figure out what makes a person a person before we could
judge whether the fetus is one, just as the field biologist must know what makes a
robin a robin before they could go out into the field and identify one.
Likewise with death. Throughout the history of medical science, there has been
an evolving definition of death. With our current analysis of persons, in terms of
their minimal psychological capacities, the ceasing of those capacities has
63
become the defining characteristic of death. So if the patient is all-but-for-thebrainstem-brain-dead, they are dead, despite the presence of a heartbeat,
breathing, and even reflex movements. Obviously, the cognitive analyses of
personhood and death have profound implications in issues of abortion and
euthanasia.
64
Dumpty thought that the only definition was a stipulative one! Lets see where
that would leave us:
Theres glory for you!
I dont know what you mean by glory, Alice said.
Humpty Dumpty smiled contemptuously. Of course
you donttill I tell you. I meant theres a nice
knock-down argument for you!
But glory doesnt mean a nice knock-down
argument, Alice objected.
When I use a word, Humpty Dumpty said, in rather a
scornful tone, it means just what I choose it to
meanneither more nor less.
The question is, said Alice, whether you can make
words mean so many different things.
The question is, said Humpty Dumpty, which is to be
masterthats all.
Alice was too much puzzled to say anything; so after a
minute Humpty Dumpty began again. Theyve a
temper, some of themparticularly verbs: theyre
the proudestadjectives you can do anything with,
but not verbshowever, I can manage the whole lot
of them! Impenetrability! Thats what I say!
Would you tell me, please, said Alice, what that
means?
Now you talk like a reasonable child, said Humpty
Dumpty, looking very much pleased. I meant by
impenetrability that weve had enough of that
subject, and it would be just as well if youd mention
what you mean to do next, as I suppose you dont
mean to stop here all the rest of your life.
Thats a great deal to make one word mean, Alice said
in a thoughtful tone.
When I make a word do a lot of work like that, said
Humpty Dumpty, I always pay it extra.
Oh! said Alice. She was too much puzzled to make
any other remark.
People seldom buy into Humpty Dumptys theory of meaning [thank goodness!],
but they still too often commit the redefinist fallacy: Rather than taking time to
argue for a conclusion, people will often just redefine it in terms of something
already granted. Its tough to argue that dogs have five legs; but it seems a lot
easier if one simply defines a tail as a leg.
65
But remember: If we call a dogs tail a leg, how many legs does a dog have?
Four! Calling a tail a leg doesnt make it one!
66
Pop quiz: You seem very clever at explaining words, Sir, said
Alice [to Humpty Dumpty]. Would you kindly tell me the
meaning of the poem called Jabberwocky?
Smart move on the part of Alice?
Persuasive definitions
Persuasive definitions are not so called because they persuade people into
adopting them by virtue of how good they are. They are so called because of
their persuasive powers despite how bad they are.
These are definitions achieved by including valued or disvalued features that
are not necessary conditions. The result is what could be called a loaded
definition.
Why would anyone do this? Well, it makes it easier to elicit value-laden
conclusions from those value-laden definitions, as they appear in the premises of
ones arguments. If one starts by defining abortion as the murder of an
innocent child prior to its birth, its remarkably easy to draw the conclusion that
abortion is always morally wrong no matter what the circumstances. But this is
only because one has included the disvalue of being a murder in the very
definition of abortion; however, murder is not a necessary characteristic of
abortion.
Ridding the definition of its unnecessary values or disvalues is called
neutralizing the definition, and if we neutralize this definition of abortion, one
is left with the rather medical definition concerning the removal of the embryonic
or fetal contents of the uterus prior to birth. And now we are left with the
abortion issue, viz., whether abortion is morally permissible or not; its not a
foregone conclusion by virtue of a stipulative definition loaded with unnecessary
value-laden conditions.
67
The moral of the story: Dont use persuasive definitions! And neutralize them
whenever they appear in an argument youre assessing for cogency.
Loaded language
This warning against loaded definitions should be extended to descriptions in
general. People use loaded language quite often, as they present their arguments.
They pack their premises with values or disvalues that are not necessary, thereby
making it much easier to draw conclusions with those same values or disvalues.
We discussed how the groundedness condition for cogency can be thought of in
terms of an arguments capacity for truth and acceptability preservationif you
put true or believable premises in the hopper of an argument meeting the
groundedness condition, you probably get true or believable conclusions coming
out the back end of it as a result. Well, the groundedness condition preserves
values and disvalues in the same way.
This is how one can rather deviously draw value-laden conclusions, either good
or bad, about someone, simply by putting the right spin on their descriptions in
the premises. In this way, one can make Mother Theresa a slacker, for never
paying taxes; or make the Unabomber a saint, for having such respect for our
environment. Ive noticed that talk-radio hosts can make a pressing ethical
dilemma out of anything, just by loading the descriptions: The topic today is
whether one ought to wade out to save a drowning infant in two feet of water.
Some say Yes, but do we really have the right to snatch another person,
without their consent, from the soft caress of the sea, at some risk of bodily harm
to them?! All of a sudden, the call-in lines are all ablaze with people who are
adamantly claiming that the only right thing to is to let the child drown! What
right do you have molesting that child and interfering with the natural flow of
events?! Thats the power of loaded language.
68
The moral of the story: Dont use loaded language! And neutralize it wherever
it appears in the argument youre assessing for cogency.
Euphemistic language
This is the error of omitting values or disvalues that are necessary for a
complete and accurate description.
Loaded language is used to make it easier to draw normative conclusions
[i.e., conclusions about what ought or ought not to be the case], while
euphemistic language is used to make it more difficult to draw normative
conclusions. For example, its tough to fault someone for working on their
proposal, unless they are more accurately described as throwing it together at
the last minute.
69
The moral of the story: Dont use euphemistic language! And neutralize it
whenever it appears in the argument youre assessing for cogency.
We see once again that Goldilocks was correct, this time with respect to
value-laden languagenot too much, not too little, but juuust right.
Fired
Tax
Failure
Explosion
Fire
The accident
Ambiguity
All my life, Ive wanted to be somebody. But now I see that I
should have been more specific. [Lily Tomlin, In Search of
Intelligent Life in the Universe]
Two very important phenomena in the language are ambiguity and vagueness.
Lets see what ambiguity is all about first.
Ambiguitywhen there are multiple definitions or meanings
of a word or phrase.
For example, the word bank has many meanings: A financial institution, the
side of a river, the action of bouncing or caroming off of [as in bank shot], to
have confidence in [as in you can bank on it]. And Im sure there are others.
Ironically, ambiguous is misused so often that its almost become ambiguous.
It is also used to say that a word or phrase is vague or unclear. This is most
unfortunate, however, because being ambiguous, being vague, and being unclear
are three quite different things, and we would do well to keep them distinct.
70
If a word or phrase is unclear, its simply that the reader or listener doesnt
understand it, for whatever reason. Its really that simple. So lets focus on what
ambiguity is now and talk about vagueness in a bit.
Many words are ambiguous, many in more than just two ways. So theres no
avoiding using ambiguous language. Ambiguity is quite a blessing, really. If we
couldnt make our words do double-duty like this, wed have to institute a
different word for each different meaning we wished to convey. What a very
different [and wordier] language wed have!
Since theres no getting out of using ambiguous language, you just have to be on
the alert to ensure that the context makes it obvious which way youre using it.
Some pretty silly things happen if youre not careful. For example, heres the
lead sentence from an Illinois newspaper, reporting the death of a man from the
town of Clinton: A 56-year-old Clinton man died as a result of something that
happened yesterday in a machine shed in Texas Township southwest of Clinton,
according to the coroners office. A natural reaction to this is to think, Well, of
course, the guy died of somethingthats no news. What would be news is if
he died of nothingthat would be worthy of an Extra: Uncaused Event
Happens in Clinton, Illinois; All Laws of Physics Proven Bankrupt! What the
newspaper was trying to say was that the Clinton man died of unknown causes;
but that intended meaning was not singled out by the choice of words, and the
result was unfortunateit undercut the credibility of the writer and might well
have offended the survivors of the poor guy from Clinton.
Ambiguity undercuts some of the most serious messages; take, for example, the
church billboard that read, Dont let worries kill you, let the church help.
Recently I saw an ad against domestic violence, consisting of a wedding picture
of a couple, and printed across the bottom of the picture was the caption, Fortytwo percent of all murdered women are killed by the same man. [Then put this
guy behind bars; youve even got his picture!] I also ran across a headline, in a
human resources department newsletter, which read, Sexual Harassment: Why
Arent People Getting It?. [I thought people didnt want it!]
Ambiguity thrives in headlines, because there is no context to disambiguate the
unfortunate phrase.
Another famous case occurred following the death of a tightrope walker, who
was crossing Niagara Falls [back when they permitted that sort of thing]. When
he was part way across, a gust of wind knocked him off the tightrope and sent
him down the falls to his death. The headline was: Man Blown to Death.
71
Here are some other headlines that slipped the leash on their authors. These
examples appear in the famous book, Squad Helps Dog Bite Victim and Other
Flubs from the Nations Press.
Old Miners Enjoy Benefits of Black Lung
Milk Drinkers Turn to Powder
Ban on Soliciting Dead in Trotwood
Fish & Game to Hold Annual Elections
Teen-age Prostitution Problem is Mounting
Man Robs, then Kills Himself
Woman Better After Being Thrown from High-Rise
Less Mishaps Than Expected Mar Holiday
Wives Kill Most Spouses in Chicago
Prostitutes Appeal to Pope
Informal fallacies
The headlines above are all honest mistakes using ambiguous terms and phrases.
But there are some dishonest mistakes too.
People use language to argue for their conclusions, but all too often people abuse
language to try to persuade their audience into believing conclusions for which
theyve been given no good reasons to believe. These rhetorical tricks are called
informal fallacies. If youre not on to them, theyre very persuasive; and thats
why they have such a long history of use. They are so infamous that theyve
even been named. So, the quicker you can identify them by name and understand
why they are fallaciousviz., why they flunk one of our ARG conditionsthe
quicker you wont fall victim to them any longer.
Well be studying about a dozen or so informal fallacies.
one involving ambiguity.
Equivocation
This informal fallacy is committed by abusing the ambiguity of a word or phrase.
Equivocationsupporting a conclusion by shifting from one
meaning of an ambiguous term to another.
Throughout our study of informal fallacies, Ill give you a basic account of what
each one is; but these definitions will probably make sense to you only after
looking at an example or two.
72
Here is a plausible-sounding argument that loving parents might well trot out
upon hearing that their daughter is thinking of pursuing a non-traditional career
as a truck driver:
Its abnormal to be a female truck driver.
Its not good to be abnormal.
Its not good to be a female truck driver.
If we assess these premises for acceptability, we find that in one sense it is true
that its abnormal to be a female truck driverviz., its infrequent. And in a
sense it is true that its not good to be abnormalviz., its not good to be
dysfunctional either physically or mentally. [Just think of those poor folks with
abnormal growths or only one oar in the water!] But is there any connection
between an events being infrequent and its being dysfunctional? No! This
argument is talking apples in the first premise and oranges in the second. Its
only by shifting from one meaning of abnormal to the otherfrom the
statistical sense of abnormal to a medical sensedoes this argument look as if
its premises build a bridge to the conclusion. But now that we see that the
premises are totally unrelated and provide no reason to believe the conclusion,
we see that the argument flunks the relevance condition for cogency. The
argument equivocates on the term abnormal.
Sometimes its so obvious that an argument equivocates that its laughable:
Ive got my money in a bank.
The bank is made of mud.
My money is stuck in mud.
But sometimes its not so obvious, and thats why people get tricked by the
fallacy of equivocation.
73
74
Vagueness
Even though people unfortunately confuse or slur together ambiguity and
vagueness, the two are quite different, and quite different still from simply being
unclear with respect to what someones saying.
Vaguenesswhen the definition of a term does not consist of
necessary and sufficient conditions.
Not all definitions are as clean cut as, for example, the definition of bachelor.
Many [most?] of our terms and concepts lack such analyses. Think about a very
famous example for a minute, an example spotted by Ludwig Wittgenstein [I kid
you not], in his Philosophical Investigations: What is a game? Try to come up
with the necessary and sufficient conditions for being a game.
If we begin thinking about paradigmatic games, we might think that an opponent
is necessary; but then solitaire comes to mind. We might think that equipment is
necessary; but then charades comes to mind. We might think that keeping score
is necessary; but then tag or catch or keep away comes to mind. We might think
that reaching some end state is necessary; and we might be right. But then this is
so vacuously true of any activity, that it just doesnt count as a distinguishing
feature of being a game.
There just doesnt seem to be an interesting necessary condition for being a
game. And if there is no substantive necessary condition, then there will be no
necessary and sufficient conditions constituting the definition of game.
75
Some games share certain features with others, and those others share certain
features with others still, but there is no one feature that all games have in
common. As Wittgenstein suggested, games are interwoven, like fibers forming
a rope; but, just like the rope, games contain no common thread.
And, lo and behold, most of our concepts and terms are like this. Try analyzing
some on your own: e.g., chair, computer, fast, or safe.
Is vague vague?
Is vague ambiguous?
Is ambiguous vague?
76
not yet quite bald. Im what is called a fuzzy case, literally and figuratively: Im
indeterminate.
What would it be like if bald and hairy were not vague terms? There would
be necessary and sufficient conditions for being bald and for being hairy. There
would be a specific number of hairs fewer than which would mean one is bald,
and a specific number of hairs greater than which would mean one is hairy. But
there simply is no such magic number of hairs! There is no magic hair the
removal of which transforms one into a bald person; and there is no magic hair
the implantation of which transforms one into a hairy person. If there were such
a magic hair, bald and hairy would be determinate; but there isnt, so they
arent. This is the defining feature of a vague term or concept.
77
Now its easy to see where the argument goes wrong. The second premise is just
plain false: just because a term is vague, and thereby indeterminate, doesnt
entail that the use of the terms is arbitrary.
Keep in mind our paradigm cases of vague terms, bald and hairy. Is it
totally arbitrary whom we may appropriately call bald or hairy? No! Clearly,
Jesse Ventura is bald! Clearly, the guys from ZZ Top are hairy. Just because we
cant draw the line between being bald and being hairy, doesnt mean anything
goes. As long as we are talking about clear-cut cases [sorry about the pun], we
have no problem appropriately identifying the extensions of bald and hairy.
Its only the fuzzy cases that stump us. But thats not our faultthose cases are
in principle indeterminate.
The moral of the story: You must use vague termsget used to it. Just be
sure to use them to refer to clear-cut cases. And with the fuzzy cases, be
intellectually honest and admit that such cases are indeterminatefor you and
for everyone.
78
But all three of the components of this definition contain elements that are purely
subjective. Whether one finds something of prurient interest, viz., sexually
arousing, is purely subjective. Whether one finds something offensive, viz.,
repulsive or revolting, is purely subjective. And whether something has any
artistic value is purely subjective. U.S. Supreme Court Justice Potter Stewart
thought he was pulling in the reins on what counts as obscene material when he
said, I may not know what it is, but I know when I see it. But he only succeeded in confessing that there are no reins at all on whats obsceneits purely
subjectivefor, similarly, he doesnt know what makes for bad-tasting food
either, he only knows it when he eats it.
So its inaccurate to argue against obscenity laws by calling them vague and
thereby unworkable. If obscene were merely vague, its use would be perfectly
workable, just as with bald and hairy and the zillion other vague terms we use
with ease everyday. Obscenity instead is purely subjective, and thats why any
laws concerning it are unworkable when they are intended to apply to all people
or even just a community of people [unless one is talking about a community
of only one person].
79
The slippery slope fallacyTo argue from the fact that one
cannot determine the exact boundaries of a terms extension,
to the conclusion that a quite liberal use, or even any
extension, of the term is appropriate.
The best way to fully understand and appreciate how the slippery slope works,
and why its so fallacious, is to closely exam a popular instance of one. The best
example I know of comes from the abortion debate [a prime source of arguments,
both good and bad].
Our current legal practices concerning the right to abortion have their foundation
in the famous Supreme Court case of Roe v. Wade. Basically it ruled that women
have the legal right to an abortion 1) before the fetus is viable [viz.,
approximately the end of the second trimester, when the fetus could be removed
and sustained with state-of-the-art artificial aid] and 2) even after viability, but
then only if the pregnancy poses a significant health risk to the pregnant woman.
This moderate position on the morality and legality of abortion is objected to by
both the pro-life advocate, who would say that all abortions, except possibly
those performed to save the life of the pregnant woman, are morally
impermissible, and the pro-choice advocate, who would say that all abortions,
even those in the third trimester, are morally permissible.
Lets begin with a slippery slope argument that is sometimes used by the prolife advocate. Our first premise is the claim that the newborn has significant
moral status. [Certainly it seems morally objectionable if the woman, moments
after giving birth, were to take the newborn tenderly in her arms and proceed to
squash it on the delivery room floor like a cigarette butt.]
Our second premise consists of a claim that stems from the fact that there was a
very gradual and continuous process of development that resulted in the
formation of the newborn from the original conceptus formed approximately nine
months earlier. This process of development is so gradual that it is difficult if not
impossible to distinguish one days development from the next. In light of this, it
would seem impossible to find a developmental difference that makes an ethical
differencea developmental difference that marks the point at which the fetus
acquired moral status. Certainly one day prior to its birth, the newborn had no
less moral status than it has at birth. For what is the difference of birth? Well, on
the day of birth, the newborn is outside the pregnant woman, while the day prior
to that the newborn was inside her. Does a change in relative location make any
moral difference? Would I lose the right to life as I walk around you, first being
on your right and then on your left? Of course not; so it looks as though we can
claim that one days difference does not make a moral difference for the
newborn. And now we can put these two premises together and draw a
conclusion:
80
And again. And again and again and again , until we finally reach the desired
conclusion:
1.
2.
3.
2.
4.
2.
5.
2.
81
If one objects to this conclusion, one must find something wrong with the argument supporting itone must find where the argument is noncogent. So where
does it flunk one of the ARG conditions?
Are the premises acceptable? Premise #1 seems true. Likewise Premise #2.
And the rest of the argument just consists of reiterations of Premise #2.
Are the premises relevant, relevant to the point of adequately grounding the
conclusion? It sure seems sothere seems to be a very smooth, logical
progression to the conclusion.
So the argument appears to meet all the ARG conditions for cogency. Are we
forced to concede, then, that the argument gives us good reason to believe the
conclusion? Not at all!
There is a bundle of problems with this slippery slope argument.
Criticism #1
Lets first demonstrate that the argument is completely unreliable in its ability
to come to a true conclusion.
Think of someone you know who has a full head of hair; lets call them Harry. If
we were to pluck one hair off Harrys head, it wouldnt make any difference, at
least no difference to Harrys still being hairy. We can describe the situation in
the following way:
1. Harry is hairy.
2. One hair less doesnt make one non-hairy. [ouch!]
3. Harry is still hairy.
But now what happens when we reiterate Premise #2 again and again and again,
each time drawing our subconclusions? Well, after many, many reiterations
[OUCH!], Harry is not only ticked-off, hes bald as a cue ball. And were still
drawing what conclusion? That Harrys still hairy!
So now we see that the slippery slope argument in support of the moral impermissibility of abortion is likewise completely unreliable, since its exactly the
same type of argument as this one that erroneously led to the view that Harrys
still hairy despite the fact that weve ripped every hair off his head.
82
Criticism #2
Our argument about Harry enables us to see a deeper flaw in the reasoning of
those who use and defend slippery slope arguments. When their conclusion is
challenged, they respond with the following counter-challenge: In order for you
object to my conclusion, you must find something wrong with my
premisesfind the false or unacceptable premise! And of course we cant.
But then do we have to find the false premise, in order to object to the slippery
slope argument?! We certainly do not, and heres why.
We know that the slippery slope argument that concludes that Harry is still hairy
is not cogent. But if someone were to demand that we find where in that
argument the premises went false, it would be a completely asinine demandit
would be the demand that we find the magic hair, the removal of which
transformed Harry from being hairy to being no longer hairy. But, of
course, there is no such magic hair! To make such a request would indicate
that one just doesnt really know what hairiness is, or at least that one fails to
appreciate that hairiness is a vague concept.
And now we see the problem with the demand that we must find the false
premise in order for us to object to the slippery slope argument that all abortions
are as morally impermissible. There simply is no such magic day of fetal
development that transforms the fetus into a being with the moral status of an
infant. To think there is such a magic day simply betrays a poor understanding of
what it is to have moral status, or at least indicates a failure to appreciate that
this too is a vague concept.
Its this fundamental misunderstanding of vague concepts that is the root of
all slippery slope fallacies. In essence, one is claiming Unless you can draw
the exact line between the appropriate use of this vague term and its
inappropriate use, you must accept my very liberal use of it. And now we know
why this is completely in error:
The inability to draw such a line never legitimizes the inappropriate use of a
vague term.
Criticism #3
Take another look at the argument:
83
1.
2.
3.
2.
4.
2.
5.
2.
Criticism #4
A fourth problem with slippery slope arguments is that they work both waysif
you can use one to get to your favorite conclusion, your opponent can use it to
slide to the opposite conclusion. Lets see how this happens.
84
We can start with the obvious truth that the sperm and the egg are not moral
entities on a par with infants. And then we add, as our second premise, that one
day more does not make a significant moral difference [again, what is the
significant difference between a right glove and a left glove and that pair of
gloves?].
After reiterating this second premise again and again and again, we get the
following:
1.
2.
3.
2.
4.
2.
5.
One cant really object to having their slippery slope argument reversed on them
like thisits their own argument, after all. Using an argument puts it in the
public domain; one cant say the likes of This argument is good, but only when I
use it.
The moral of the story: Dont use slippery slope arguments! Thats why they
are slippery slope fallacies!
85
86
Pop quiz: Think about various issues in the news and see if you
can spot slippery slope fallacies as they crop up during debates
in ethics and social policy. Here are some topics to get you
started.
gun control
alcohol consumption
religious freedom
freedom of speech
87
Acceptability
6. ACCEPTABILITY
Lets start our detailed study of the ARG conditions for cogency, beginning with
the requirement that the premises of an argument be acceptable.
88
Acceptability
and on and on. And since this regress is infinite, it never gets completed; which
means that we could never have acceptable premises; which means that none of
our arguments is ever cogent.
But hold on there! Certainly not all of our arguments suck! Some of our arguments are cogent; so, some of our premises must be acceptable.
So this particular analysis of the acceptability requirement must be mistaken.
89
Acceptability
90
Acceptability
My belief that, generally, when things look like computers and logos and words,
they are real computers and logos and words, is based on many, many other
beliefsperceptual beliefs and various other kinds of background beliefs. For
example:
Based on this simple example alone, then, we can easily see that there will be no
such thing as a foundation of self-evident beliefs for us to use as our sole or
ultimate source of acceptability.
91
Acceptability
92
Acceptability
premise that a child, for example, has absolutely no reason at their disposal to
think is true. You have much more experience and background knowledge than
the child does, and you can call upon that background as justification for
believing your premises; the child cant.
So, if you want your arguments to meet the acceptability condition for a wider
audience than just yourself, your strategy should be to make your premises as
uncontroversial and as unquestionable as possible. Use premises that do not
presuppose extraordinary amounts of background knowledge.
This presents a challenge at times: You want to reach the widest possible
audience with your arguments, so you provide premises that even those with a
very moderate degree of background knowledge would find acceptable.
But you then run the risk of dummying down your argument to the point to
which your premises are so trivially true that youre insulting your audience by
talking to them as if they were children.
Use the Goldilocks strategy again as you pick your premises: Not too esoteric;
not too platitudinous; but rather, juuuust right for your audience.
93
Acceptability
Subarguments
You might find your premises acceptable, by virtue of your background beliefs
that are acting as your reasons for thinking your premises are true. But if your
audience doesnt share that background, you must provide them with it. And
thats how subarguments get generated. You knowwhat we studied in the
Anatomy of an Argumentwhen conclusions become premises for further
conclusions.
Sometimes we need to provide reasons in support of our reasons for our
conclusions. And sometimes, we even need to provide reasons for believing
those reasons. And sometimes,well, you get the idea. Whatever it takes to
get your audience to finally have more reason to believe your conclusion than not
to believe it, thats what you need to provide.
94
Acceptability
95
Acceptability
96
Acceptability
97
Acceptability
Whos an authority?
Sometimes the so-called experts arent the real experts and the real experts are
the least recognizable. Being able to know which are which often presupposes a
lot of background knowledge that the average person doesnt have. Catch-22!
For example, during the cold war, the so-called experts in the State Department
negotiating nuclear disarmament may not have been the real experts at all; we
just lucked out because of the USSRs failing budget. The real experts might
well have been the math geeks in decision theory, who had long ago proved that
the tit-for-tat negotiating strategy would result in total disarmament, assuming
merely that our two countries cared only for themselves and were not suicidal.
But who knew?!
The appeal to authority for one person is often the appeal to false authority for
another. For example, many people appeal to their religious leaders and religious
texts as guides on ethical matters. While these may be religious authorities, they
cannot function as authorities on ethics, for the general public. The general rule
about adopting premises is especially important when applied to appeals to
authority: Keep your audiences background beliefs in mind, so that your
premises are acceptable to the widest possible audience.
Unacceptable!
Seven of Nine never seemed to pass up the opportunity to make this charge on
Star Trek Voyager. Lets examine four of the various ways that premises can be
unacceptablewhen those premises are:
98
Acceptability
99
Acceptability
that they dont know what the argument is saying, rather than that they know that
the argument is both saying something and denying it simultaneously.
To assert and deny a statement simultaneously is a huge blunder. But it does
happen, so you have to be on the alert for it. Heres an example to illustrate [see
if you can find the contradiction].
[The problem with having pornography establishments in ones
community] concerns the tone of the society, the mode, or to use
terms that have perhaps greater currency, the style and quality of
life, now and in the future. A man may be entitled to read an
obscene book in his room, or expose himself indecently there....
We should protect his privacy. But if he demands a right to
obtain the books and pictures he wants in the market and to
foregather in public placesdiscreet, if you will, but accessible
to allwith others who share his tastes, then to grant him his
right is to affect the world about the rest of us, and to impinge
on others privacies. Even supposing that each of us can, if he
wishes, effectively avert the eye and stop the ear (which, in truth,
we cannot), what is commonly read and seen and heard and done
intrudes upon us all, want it or not. [Bickel, quoted in Majority
Opinion in Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, Chief Justice Warren
Burger]
This was a rather ingenious argument for the States right to censor pornography
as it is shown in places of public accommodation, such as theaters: Establish
such pornography as a form of publicly displayed pornography, on a par with
pornographic billboards that have a captive audience. And virtually everyone
agrees with the States right to prohibit pornography that one is forced to see; so
therefore, everyone should agree to prohibiting pornography as shown in places
of public accommodation.
The problem with this argument is that there is a contradiction within the
premises: The pornography in places of public accommodation is called
discreet and yet shown in such a way that one cannot avert the eyeviz., the
author is saying one is not forced to look at it and forced to look at it.
100
Acceptability
While people seldom use contradictory premises within a single argument, they
quite often use contradictory premises across multiple arguments. Sometimes
this is unintentional absentmindedness, but sometimes it is done purely for the
devious purpose of rationalizing conclusions, as opposed to justifying them.
Dealing with this kind of intellectual dishonesty is very frustrating.
For example, I recently had to work with a committee that was deciding which
courses should be categorized as Different Culture for the Universitys new
general education program. All and only courses dedicated to the study of
different cultures were to admitted into this categorythats the only requirement. Classical Philosophy had always been in this category, and the committee
agreed that ancient Greek civilization was drastically different from our own in
terms of beliefs, values, and social and political practicesthe admitted core
aspects of a culture.
The committee agreed that African Americans do not differ markedly in these
respects; in fact, it would be rather racist to think so. The committee also agreed
that women do not differ markedly in these respects either; in fact, it would be
rather sexist to think so. While having a different language is sometimes an
indicator of a different culture, the committee agreed that, due to the
globalization of the economy and most other aspects of our lives, the U.S.,
Europe, and Latin and South America differ little overall in terms of beliefs,
values, etc.
From among the courses on the following topics, then, which should have been
granted Different Culture designation by the committee?
1.
2.
3.
4.
101
Acceptability
When all the inconsistencies of these arguments were pointed out [can you count
them all?], the committee gladly admitted that their decisions were inconsistent,
as if to say But thats not a flaw; thats a feature. Indeed, more and more I find
people taking pride in their inconsistencies; in fact, they regularly quote Walt
Whitmans Leaves of Grass, as their contradictions are pointed out to them: Do
I contradict myself? Very well thenI contradict myself.
What can you do with such a person who refuses to honor the most fundamental
law of thoughtconsistency? There is really nothing you can do. Just walk
away, recommends Aristotle: We cannot be expected to argue with such a person, any more than we can be expected to convince a vegetable. And so, walk
away is just what I did.
Pop quiz: One committee member pointed out that: The new
title for the different culture category is actually Multicultural
Perspectives; so, since Classical Philosophy studies only one
culture, instead of multiple ones, it should be rejected. I had to
laugh out loud. Why?
102
Acceptability
A classic is a 1970 magazine ad for Volvo. The ad claimed that 9 out of every
10 Volvos registered here in the last eleven years are still on the road. This
naturally set up the inference that Volvos are pretty darn reliable. And since
most people in the market for a car are searching for a reliable one, the practical
conclusion to draw is I better seriously consider buying a Volvo. But this
argument rested on a false assumption; an assumption that was almost unavoidable in light of how the ad was worded.
The false assumption was that Volvos were sold in the U.S. for quite some time.
They werent. They were sold in the U.S. as of 1959. They had only been sold
in the U.S. for eleven years, with the vast majority of them sold in those years
just prior to the appearance of the ad.
And now that were wise to the ad and stop relying on the false assumption, we
realize that Volvos record of reliability was no better than the competitions.
Sometimes, the arguments false assumption is so well hidden that one could
barely be expected to find it. A great example of this is a television ad that aired
during the late 1980s. [I remember watching the ad, but I prefer to mention no
names.] The ad consisted of a long description of how brand MH coffee was
overwhelmingly preferred over brand F in a huge double-blind taste test that was
carried out all over the country at various locations such as shopping malls. The
inference that was so natural to make at the end of this ad was, If so many
people preferred brand MH over brand F, then I should buy MH next time Im at
the grocery store shopping for coffee, since I want the better-tasting coffee.
The false assumption working behind this ad is that the coffee used in the taste
test was the same as the shopper finds on the grocery store shelves. While that
assumption held true for the brand F, it was not true for the MH coffee. The
corporation owning brand MH bought gourmet coffee to use as its coffee in the
taste test. No wonder it was preferred!
103
Acceptability
104
Acceptability
105
Acceptability
If you leave your premises no more believable than your conclusion, and if your
conclusion happens to be quite unbelievable, then be prepared to have someone
reverse the argument on you, arguing that one of your premises is suspect.
The following little example will show you what I mean:
Everywhere that Mary went, her lamb was sure to
follow. And Mary was at the party, so the lamb was
there too.
Now imagine that someone objects by saying the following:
Well, I was looking for Mary at the party all night and
didnt bump into her. And Im allergic to sheep. So I
would have noticed a lamb at the party! But I agree with
you that Mary and that lamb of hers are always
togetherits weird! And thats why I dont think Mary
was even there.
Here someone has argued against my second premise. Alternatively, heres how
someone might argue that my first premise is suspect.
I doubt that Marys lamb was therethey dont even
allow cats in the house! But I do think I saw Mary. So I
bet Mary and that lamb of hers have finally parted ways
a bit.
So make sure you provide acceptable reasons for thinking your conclusion is true,
or your audience might well reverse the argument on you and provide you with
stinging reasons for thinking your premises are false.
106
Acceptability
107
Acceptability
Conditional arguments
1. Assume that the University once again fails to get a
real budget increase.
2. In that case, there will be a freeze on staff hirings.
3. If that happens, computer service will only get worse.
4. If the University doesnt get a substantial budget
increase, then computer service is going to
deteriorate.
This is called a conditional argument, because of the form of the conclusion;
its a conditional statementan if, then statement. On the basis of these
premises, could one conclude that the Universitys computer service will be
getting worse? No. One can draw that conclusion only under the assumption
stated in the first premise: If that assumption is true, then computer service goes
into the toilet.
Whats the good of such a limited conclusion? Well, sometimes you dont know
exactly what to believe about your circumstancesit could be one thing or
maybe another. And so you dont know exactly what to conclude. But that
neednt stop you from investigating various implications of various possibilities,
for planning purposes. Sometimes, in times of uncertainty [and which times
arent?!] conditional conclusions are all you can draw, in preparation for when
the truth of your premises is finally settled.
Reductio ad absurdum
A reductio ad absurdum, or reductio, as its called for short, is best understood
as a type of criticisma criticism against either an argument or a position.
Reductio ad absurdum is Latin for reduced to absurdity. And thats what one
is trying to do to the targeted argument or positionshow that its absurd to
adopt it.
108
Acceptability
It begins by assuming, purely for the sake of discussion, that certain statements
are true. If the reductio is directed at an argument, assume for the sake of
discussion that its premises are true. If the reductio is directed at a position,
simply assume for the sake of argument that that position is true.
Next, the reductio details some of the implications of those assumptions; more
specifically, it details some of the implications that are inconsistent or just
patently false. Lets illustrate the reductio by using an example drawn once again
from the well of the abortion debatea deep well of bad reasoning by all sides of
the issue. Lets look at the popular Sanctity of Life Argument [SLA] against
abortion on demand.
This argument claims that all human life is sacreda gift of God. And, as a gift
of God, only God can take back such a life. That is why the taking of a human
life during an abortion on demand is morally impermissible.
Assuming these premises are true, for the sake of our investigation, what else is
implied by them? What other conclusions are equally well supported?
Well, lets trace some out.
The sanctity of human life is not a function of how that life was brought about.
The origin of the fetus has no bearing on its sacred statuswhether it comes
from Cleveland, for example, makes no moral difference. And that it came about
as the result of rape or incest should be equally irrelevant, then. In light of this,
however, abortions in the case of rape and incest should be construed as being
just as morally objectionable as abortions on demand. But this contradicts the
usual position adopted by the advocates of the SLA, which makes an exception to
the moral impermissibility of abortion in cases of rape and incest.
What if the pregnancy becomes life-threatening in such a way that, tragically,
one but only one can survive the situationif the pregnancy continues, the
woman will die and the fetus is rescued; if the abortion is performed, the fetus is
sacrificed and the womans life is saved. There are two lives of equal sanctity
now in the balance. The SLA has no means of distinguishing between the two,
favoring one over the other. In such cases of equal claims, each claim must be
given an equal chancesuch an impartial means of deciding would be, for
example, flipping a coin. But this too contradicts the usual position adopted by
the advocates of the SLA, which makes an exception to the moral impermissibility of abortion in the case of life-threatening pregnancies. Moreover, to
conclude that abortions in the case of life-threatening pregnancies should be
decided by means of a coin-flip is patently false, wildly absurd. Thats, however,
where the SLA leads us.
109
Acceptability
Things get even worse for the SLA. It ultimately implies that all lethal cases of
self-defense or the use of lethal force in the life-saving defense of others is
immorala taking of a sacred life, which only God is allowed to do.
But, of course, this is absolutely absurdthere are perfectly permissible cases of
self-defense and defense of others by lethal means. In fact, some such cases
would arguably be our moral duty!
So there must be something wrong with the SLA. It may have first appeared
reasonable, but we now see that it is a loose cannon, spraying out patently absurd
conclusions. We see that the SLA is completely unreliable as a means to the
truth.
The victim of our reductio is left with three options:
1. Keep their original argument, and deny the new implication.
But: If the new implication is as well supported by the
argument as their original conclusion is, then this option
would entail that they are inconsistentusing their argument
when it leads them to conclusions they like, but not using it
when it leads them to conclusions they dont like.
2. Keep their original argument and avoid being inconsistent by
embracing the new implication toobiting the bullet, lets
call it. But: This would mean adopting a patent
falsehoodadopting something that is wildly, absurdly
false. [Hence the name!]
3. Avoid being inconsistent and avoid being forced to adopt an
absurd implication by simply giving up the argument.
What is getting them between the rock of inconsistency and
the hard place of implying an absurd falsehood is their
argument. By getting rid of the argument, they get rid of the
problem. But: Giving up ones argument means that ones
conclusion is thereby reduced to a mere assertion.
So, when someone hands you an argument, ask two very important
questions:
What are the implications of this argument? Find
implications that are indeed as equally-well supported by
the argument as the original conclusion is. This
forecloses on the first option listed
aboveinconsistency is not an option!
110
Acceptability
Pop quiz:
The SLA is usually amended in an attempt to avoid the
reductios we just constructed. One amendment has
classically been called the Double Effect Argument,
which stipulates that of all the effects that are caused by
our actions, we are to be morally judged on only the
intended effects, rather than the unintended [and often
regretted] effects. Adding this argument to the SLA, one
can then avoid the implications that abortion in cases of
rape or incest or in cases of life-threatening pregnancy
are morally objectionable, because in those cases the
intention behind the abortion is to save the woman from
further pain of the sexual assault or to save the life of the
pregnant woman; the intention is not to kill the fetus,
even though one knows this will regrettably result.
How many reductios can you find against the Double Effect
Argument?
111
Acceptability
As our target, lets use the Golden Rule: Do unto others as you would have them
do unto you. This has long been believed to be a pretty good guide to ethical
behavior and to promoting happiness in society. And, indeed, it works a fair
portion of the time. But, as a principle, it has some major flaws which work as
reductios to this position on how to promote happiness and morality.
For example, the first time I was with my wife, Ann, when she became ill, I
wanted to make her as comfortable and as happy as possible, so I consciously
applied the Golden Rule, asking How would I like to be treated when Im
feeling like crap? I like to be left totally alone; I dont want to bother with
people wondering how Im doing. So thats how I treated her. Big mistake! She
likes lots of attention when shes sick; she likes to be checked on frequently; she
likes lots of poor baby!s.
The first time I was sick, she too consulted the Golden Rule to figure out what
she could do for me. I thought Id die!
Other reductios can be generated by simply citing some pretty nasty and masochistic things people might like done to themselves. The Golden Rule would
deem them morally permissible to do to others, and thats just wrong.
Here, then, is the basic format for building reductios:
Find implications:
Cite absurdity:
Reject target:
Confession: One of the most refreshing things you can do when applying your
critical thinking skills is to deliver a stinging reductio. It is the most powerful
tool of criticism at your disposal. Long-reigning theories in science, religion,
ethics, you name it, have come tumbling down because of reductios. It doesnt
matter who you are, who you know, or how much money you have, this critical
tool is always at your disposal to help you cut through the errors and get closer to
the truth. Andit feels pretty good too, when you can reduce some pompous gas
bag to absurdity.
112
Acceptability
113
Acceptability
Re. 1. Almost all experiments in all the sciences are done under
artificial conditions, but it is absurd to think they are
unilluminating and unreliable for that.
Re. 2. It is true of every law, that it might be used to advance
the self-interests of those enforcing them. But it is absurd
to think that these laws should be abolished for
thatwed be left with no laws!
Re. 3. If the fetus total dependence on the pregnant woman
gives her the right to end that relation by killing the fetus,
the same would be true of the newborn or even the young
child, who is totally dependent on someone or other for
its very existence. But it is absurd to think that one can
kill, e.g., a two-year-old the moment it becomes totally
dependent on one, simply because it is so dependent.
Re. 4. If sentience is what wins creatures rights, then livestock
have rights to the same degree as people do, and those
raising livestock are morally equivalent to the Nazis. But
that is absurd, even if sentience is a sufficient condition
for lesser degrees of moral consideration.
114
Acceptability
115
Acceptability
Here is an argument for the conclusion that there is no soul that is responsible for
our actions; there is no spiritual entity that is causing our bodily movements. It
consists of two premises: 1) Only physical objects can cause physical events,
such as the movement of the body. 2) The soul is a spiritual objecta nonphysical object. And thats why its just not the kind of thing that can cause
actions, unlike the kind of thing the brain is.
The flaw with this argument is that the first premise, about what alone can cause
physical events such as bodily movements, already rules out souls as possible
causes. So the argument commits what fallacy? Thats right, the fallacy of
begging the question. But how would one argue for that first premise? We
would run into the same problem as we witnessed earlier, if we just appealed to
our vast experience of physical objects that do cause physical eventsits not a
sample big enough to rule out souls doing it too.
We soon realize that this premise is a fundamental assumptiona basic position
in a world view we call physicalism. It is the view that all physical, natural
phenomena are the result of physical, natural laws and relations and that there are
no external, supernatural influences on these phenomena. This is the basic belief
of science. The denial of this premise is what we call dualism. Dualism is the
position that there are two kinds of entities, physical and spiritual, and that they
can interactphysical events causing spiritual events and spiritual events
causing physical events.
The physicalist usually argues for physicalism by claiming that the dualist is
unscientific. And the dualist usually argues for dualism by claiming that the
physicalist is closed minded. But, of course, this just amounts to each camp
begging the question against the other during this name calling. What each camp
needs is enough intellectual honesty to at least admit their respective fundamental
assumptions are just that, fundamental assumptions.
But the physicalist can do more than that. They can do a reductio on the denial
of their first premise, and thereby do a reductio on dualism. Heres how.
Assume for the sake of argument that dualism is trueassume that not only
physical objects can cause physical events, but non-physical objects can too.
The soul or spiritual self is non-physical, and thus, according to the dualist, is not
fettered with the same limitations that physical objects are. For example,
spiritual objects dont have mass, evidenced by the absurdity of wondering how
much ones soul weights [an ounce; a pound?!]. Moreover, they dont have
spatial location either, evidenced by the absurdity of wondering where your soul
is [behind your ear; in your left foot; up your butt?!]. The soul, according to the
dualist, doesnt need mass to cause events in the physical world, and it doesnt
116
Acceptability
need to be in contact with the physical object it affects in order to affect it. And
now we are ready to begin drawing implications.
If indeed the physicalist is wrong and the dualist is right, then not only should my
soul be able to cause my body to move at my will and your soul cause your body
to move at your will, but, with equal ease, my soul should cause your body to
move at my will, and your soul should cause my body to move at your will.
After all, my soul shouldnt just move my body because its near it; my soul is
not near any bodyits nowhere at all.
But, of course, these across-individuals causal relations are not equally probable.
[I order you to send me all your money immediately! See? Nothing.] So
dualism cant be right; only physical objects can be causing physical events such
as our actions. And thats why our minds must be, in some sense, identical to our
brains, in order to be in control of our bodies.
So, if you cant argue for your position without begging the question, try
doing a reductio on its denial.
That concludes our discussion of the first of our cogency conditions, the acceptability of premises. Its time to move on to the second condition: The relevance
of those premises.
117
Relevance
7. RELEVANCE
An argument is supposed to be a conduit of truth and acceptability. And thats
the job of the relevance condition for cogencyto make sure the acceptability
of the premises, to some degree at least, gets transferred to the conclusion.
Premises are relevant to the degree that they provide reason to believe their conclusions. So premises can get by rather cheaply sometimes and still meet the
relevance condition, since all they have to do it to provide some reason to
believe the conclusion.
Remember, seeing one measly chickadee eat one measly sunflower seed enables
me to meet the relevance condition as I draw the broad conclusion that chickadees prefer sunflower seeds over any other food. Its more reason than I had
prior to that observation [when I had no reason at all!].
Another way of characterizing the relevance condition is that the truth of the
premises increases the probability that the conclusion is true. Again, it
doesnt have to increase it by much; it just has to increase it.
Irrelevance
So whats it like to flunk the relevance condition? Embarrassing.
Its when the truth of the conclusion is independent of the truth of the
premises.
Its when the connection between the premises and the conclusion is so out of
whack that the truth or falsity of the premises doesnt matter to the truth or
falsity of the conclusion.
An argument falling victim to this plight is said to be a non sequitur. This is
Latin for That doesnt follow! Here are some examples:
I should not be given such a low grade for this course. This
course is only an elective, its only a 100-level course, and I get
high grades in all the courses for my major.
You shouldnt do that! What if everyone did that? Wed be in a
fine fix then, wouldnt we?
In response to recently proposed closures of sensitive sand dune
areas on Bureau of Land Management tracts to protect endemic
118
Relevance
deductive arguments
arguments by analogy
inductive generalizations
arguments by subsumption
119
Relevance
Remember how deductive validity by itself does not guarantee that the
premises are relevant? Validity is just a relation between the premises and the
conclusion such that at no time could the premises be true and the conclusion
false. But that relation can hold with no help from the truth of the premises.
Bill Clinton was president; therefore, 2 + 2 = 4, is a valid argument; but its
premise does not give us a reason for believing the conclusion.
So when we claim that an argument is valid because its premises guarantee its
conclusion, we are saying that it is both valid and meets relevance condition.
For deductive arguments, relevance is going to be all or nothingeither the truth
of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion or it doesnt. Either the
premises entail the conclusion or they are irrelevant. This is because of the
strong claim of a deductive argument. It doesnt claim to make its conclusion
probably true, given the truth of its premises; it claims to make its conclusion
true, given the truth of its premises.
So if a deductive argument is invalid, its also a non sequitur.
120
Relevance
121
Relevance
would mean you are making a distinction between these two actionsa
distinction where you have just confessed there is no difference.
Thats the power of an argument by analogy: If your audience agrees with your
premises, youve gotem!
Lets go back to J.J. Thomsons famous argument and see how it fits into our
schematic.
target:
you
the violinist
fatal kidney ailment
the kidnapping
the Society of Music Lovers
plugging in
unplugging
What if someone were to point out that violinists and fetuses are so different that
this just doesnt make any sense; after all, violinists play the violin and fetuses
dont? The proper response is that this difference is irrelevant. An argument by
analogy just requires that the two cases be alike in all relevant respects; they
dont have to be alike in all respects, period. Here the only relevant respects are
those that have to do with ones moral status and ones right to be treated in
certain ways. And certainly, being able to play the violin does not win one any
more or less moral status. Similarly, violinists generally have more hair than
fetuses; but thats not a relevant difference either.
122
Relevance
As you construct your arguments from analogy, use our basic format as a
checklist:
Regarding premise #1: Find a clear-cut case. For example, if
you are arguing for the conclusion that a certain action is morally
impermissible, find an analogous action that is clearly morally
wrongone that everyone except the pathologically amoral
would agree with. How about this: Shooting the elderly for
sport is wrong. We have hunting season on deer and it has its
benefits, especially for us rural drivers [collisions with deer
being the most frequent type of auto accident]. And, from a
macabre point of view, having hunting season on seniors would
have its social benefits tooit would go some way towards
solving the social security issue; it would speed up the lines at
the supermarket, etc. But no matter; it would be just plain
unethical! And anyone who would even hesitate to admit
this,well, dont invite them to your partytheyre beyond the
pale!
Regarding premise #2: Make sure your analogy is a good
one. Make sure your analog and your target are alike in all
relevant respects. Make sure your analogy is on all fours.
As you critique arguments from analogy, use this same checklist to form your
critical questions:
Regarding premise #1: Is this a clear-cut case? If not, the
argument by analogy doesnt get off the launch pad.
Regarding premise #2: Is there any relevant difference
between the two cases? This question is important because, if
there is such a relevant difference, one could very well agree
with the arguments claim about the analog but yet disagree with
the conclusions claim about the target, without being
inconsistent.
False analogy
If either of these premises is false or unacceptable, the argument commits the
informal fallacy of false analogythe premise regarding the so-called analogous
case is irrelevant to the conclusion about the target case.
For example, what about the following argument?
123
Relevance
124
Relevance
125
Relevance
126
Relevance
But this appeal to the general principle that ones right to free speech ought not to
be infringed upon is totally irrelevant, because this guy was not saying anything
by wiping off his dipstick with the flag; he was just changing his oil. Wiping off
his dipstick was not a form of speechhe was not expressing a political protest.
There are plenty of reasons why he should be allowed to use a discarded U.S.
flag as a grease rag; its just that the exercise of his right to free speech isnt one
of them here.
It seems to me that this sort of thing happens quite oftenpeople appeal to
ethical or legal principles that in fact are irrelevant. For purposes of discussion,
let me give you a more controversial example:
The most popular argument against the censorship of pornography is that it
violates its producers right to freedom of speech. And yet this ethical or
constitutional right is relevant only if pornography is a form of speech. Is it?
What is said by pornography?
Not, what is intimated by pornography? For pornography intimates many
things, one of which is the view that women are the fit targets of sexual abuse.
[And the producers of pornography have consistently denied intending that
message.] Many actions intimate or indicate things without stating them; for
example, my neighbors failure to take in his garbage can indicates that hes
lazy, but his leaving his garbage can out is not his saying to me or to anyone
Im lazy. So let me repeat the question: What is pornography saying, or
what are the producers of pornography saying, to the consumers? Kind of
puzzling, once you think about it!
Well, maybe this will help: What is the function of pornography? Is it like Time
magazine, a clear-cut case of a form of speech, telling its readers things? Thats
a stretch! Whats its function, then? Well, basically to sexually arouse its
consumers. In light of this discovery, its no mystery why those other items are
usually sold in porn shopsthose novelties or marital aids. Their sole
function too is sexual arousal.
Now, make believe that the government wanted to confiscate such novelties. [I
can hear the likes of Charlton Heston now: The only way the governments
going to get my dildo is to pry it from my cold, dead hands!] Would one appeal
to the right to freedom of speech to argue against it? Hardly! Theres no speech
involved here [other than perhaps the directions on the box about how to put the
batteries in, but thats not what were interested in protecting].
And so it is with pornographyits as silly to appeal to ones right to free speech
to protect it as it is to appeal to the right free speech in order to protect ones use
of marital aids. What appeal would be relevant? Well, how about an appeal to
ones generic right to libertythe right to own and do what one wishes so long
127
Relevance
as doing so does not infringe on the rights of others. This is indeed an important,
applicable ethical and legal principle. The debate about pornography, then,
focuses where it shouldon the interesting, complex empirical issue of whether
or not the consumption of some forms of pornography increases the disposition
of some men to aggress and discriminate against women. The censorship issue is
not thereby settled; rather, the debate about it is finally relevant.
Straw man
Ad hominem
Guilt by association
Appeal to ignorance
Appeal to popularity
Appeal to force
Straw man
Whats fishy about the following little argument?
The legislation prohibiting cigarette machines and requiring
elaborate proof of age is not a good idea. Do they really expect
this to stop every adolescent from getting cigarettes? How
ridiculous!
If indeed the advocates of this legislation did think this was a way of stopping
adolescent smoking, they would be ridiculously wrong. But that was not their
128
Relevance
129
Relevance
130
Relevance
of any weaker versions of their targets. A straw man fallacy is committed when
one successfully criticizes a weaker version of ones opponent, claiming those
criticisms work equally well against all stronger versions too, when in fact they
dont. This variety of straw man has all the intellectual honesty of claiming you
climbed a mountain, when you only walked its foothills.
Another way of committing the straw man fallacy is to give an unsuccessful
reductio ad absurdum criticism. Heres why a fizzled reductio is properly diagnosed as a straw man: When your reductio fails, its because the position or
argument youve targeted either fails to have the implication you claimed it does
or its implication is not absurdly false as you claimed it is. In either case, you
have misrepresented your opponents position or argument as having an absurd
implication when in fact it does not.
Ad hominem
Literally translated from the Latin, this is Attack on the man.
Bill Clintons China trade policies were completely bankrupt.
The only foreign affairs he would have been competent at was
having sex in the Oval Office with an Asian intern.
This is a typical, blatant case of an ad hominem; and now you see why its so
named.
Ad hominemwhen derogatory charges are made against
the advocate of a position or argument, using those charges
as reasons to claim that the position is false or the argument
is not cogent.
What do ya mean, pornography is disrespectful of women?
Where do you get that feminist clap-trap anyway? Youve been
in that Women Studies course too long; its starting to affect
your brain. Youre in that course just to meet chicks, I know it!
There are a couple ad hominems in this example: The guys mental health is
questioned and his motives are being questionedhe is being called an opportunist for learning a thing or two in a Womens Studies course. The critic is
lobbing insults at him rather than critically reviewing his claim that pornography
is disrespectful of women. The author of this claim is attacked instead of the
claim itself. And thats the ad hominem.
The ad hominem fallacy is a way of flunking the relevance condition, and heres
how you can tell: Even if the derogatory charges against the person were
131
Relevance
true, it would not provide any evidence whatsoever against the persons
position or argument.
Lets illustrate: Assume, just for the sake of argument, that the guy in our
example is thinking with his heart instead of his head, and lets also assume that
indeed the main reason he took the Womens Studies course is to meet chicks;
especially chicks that aint afraid to spring for the check now and then. Is that
any evidence against his claim that pornography is disrespectful of women? Not
in the least; that explanation as to why hes making his claim is totally independent of the truth of his claim.
Those who favor putting restrictions on abortion are just a bunch
of old fart conservatives who think women ought to be on their
backs or by a stove!
Lets illustrate how this ad hominem is irrelevant. Even if it were true that all
those who think that abortion is unethical are old farts who also think that women
should be relegated to purely domestic roles, that would not be any reason to
believe that abortion is ethical.
Men would not be so anti-abortion if they got pregnant!
Another ad hominem. Indeed it is probably true that if men got pregnant too,
they would be more inclined to advocate abortion rights, but that is no reason to
think that abortions are ethical.
To improve your ability to spot ad hominems, there are two things to keep firmly
in mind:
The truth of ones position is independent of ones motive or
explanation for having that position.
The cogency of ones argument is independent of ones motive
or explanation for giving that argument.
Thats why attacking the motives or background of the advocate of the
position or argument is irrelevant.
Species of ad hominem
FYI: There are various ways of committing the ad hominem. Whats crucial is
that you simply be able to recognize an ad hominem when you bump into one
and, of course, to not commit one! Being familiar with some of the specific
kinds of ad hominem arguments, however, can only help you do this.
132
Relevance
133
Relevance
Distinction alert!
There is a difference between being hypocritical and being
inconsistent. The former just means one doesnt live up to ones
own claims, which does not entail that those claims are false.
The latter, however, means ones claims are contradictory, which
does entail that some of those claims are false. Thats why
134
Relevance
135
Relevance
And now what did you have for breakfast this morning?
Two donuts and a pot of coffee, thats what!
136
Relevance
Guilt by association
This informal fallacy is a close cousin to the ad hominem, because it too involves
mudslinging. But there is a subtle difference.
Guilt by associationto place an author or a position in a
group of disreputable standing; by so doing, the audience is
tempted to attribute that same disreputable characteristic to
the author or position.
This fallacy is a favorite of politicians, especially during elections. Two classic
examples happened during the Bush-Dukakis presidential campaign.
George Bushs comment that Michael Dukakis was a card-carrying member of
the American Civil Liberties Union, was a very effective way of driving voters
away from his opponent. This comment was made to the media at a time when
the ACLU, a legal-defense organization, was arguing before a high court for
peoples right to child pornography. This invited the average person to make the
following inference:
1. The ACLU is currently defending child pornography.
2. Dukakis is a member of the ACLU.
3. Dukakis defends child pornography!
But, of course, one can be a member of a group and still not advocate everything
that group doesin fact, thats usually the case. In the context of Bushs comment, however, many listeners werent going to remember this truism. They
137
Relevance
were too busy thinking: That bastard! How can he defend something so
horrible! The dirt of the group was successfully rubbed off on Dukakis.
There was another, more subtle, instance of guilt by association occurring in
Bushs comment. Can you discover it?
Heres a hint: Who else were called card-carrying members? That phrase is
strongly associated with Communism. Senator Joe McCarthy kicked off many
hearings before his House Committee on Un-American Activities with the
question Are you now or have you ever been a card-carrying member of the
Communist Party? That phrase is so strongly associated with Communism, that
many people find it psychologically impossible to keep from dragging that notion
along when the phrase is applied to other matters. Check it out: Are you now
or have you ever been a card-carrying member of the Nobel Prize Laureates?
Even as great an honor as the Nobel Prize sounds dastardly now.
Another example was the famous Willie Horton television ad. The ad included a
mug shot of Willie Horton, a rather tough-looking black man. The ad described
how Horton had received week-end passes from prison through a furlough
program, while he was serving a life-sentence for murder. During a weekend
release, he kidnapped a couple, stabbed the man and repeatedly raped the
woman. The ad also pointed out that Dukakis was an advocate of the program.
This, then, invited the average viewer to make the following inference:
1. Dukakis favors a furlough program.
2. This program enabled Willie Horton to rape and attack.
3. Dukakis favors programs that enable prisoners to rape and attack.
Obviously, one can be in favor of a program or a policy and still not favor everything that unintentionally and unforeseeably results from it. Many viewers,
however, forgot thisthey were too busy falling victim to the fallacy, thinking:
That SOB! How can he favor what Willie Hortons done?!
BTW: You can watch all the classic campaign ads on the Web
at http://www.ammi.org Especially after completing this
chapter, critically review these ads and see if you can spot all the
fallacies.
People who use the fallacy of guilt by association are taking advantage of the fact
that people are not careful with their inferences. That a disreputable party is
associated with a belief or value or action is, by itself, irrelevant to its truth or
worth.
138
Relevance
Heres a strange, extreme case that may help you keep this in mind: Hitler was a
firm advocate of breathing and supported the idea that 2+2 = 4; but certainly, we
would never conclude that breathing and arithmetic are suspect as a result of this
association.
Disrepute is in the eye of the beholder, come time to judge whether or not the
fallacy of guilt by association has been committed. An example will illustrate
my point. I remember hearing a U.S. legislator give the following little speech
early in the Clinton years:
The issue before us today is whether to pass the Presidents
health-care bill, a copy of which I have in my hand. I want you
to know that I am against this bill. I dislike the way the First
Lady has gotten involved in this legislative process. Who
elected her, anyway?
By snuggling the bill up to the Hilary Clinton, the legislator was hoping that the
audiences dislike for her would rub off on the bill. The fallacy worked only on
those who viewed the First Lady unfavorably. And so it is that youll find
religious groups arguing against something by pointing out that the atheists are in
favor of it, and atheists arguing against something by pointing out that religious
groups are in favor of it. In either case, though, its still the same fallacy.
Beware: When people point out cases of strange bedfellows, they are often
committing the fallacy of guilt by association.
139
Relevance
140
Relevance
Appeal to ignorance
Until someone proves to me that there was no conspiracy to kill
John F. Kennedy, Im going to continue believing that the
Warren Commission was wrong in their finding against the
conspiracy theory. In fact, Im inclined to think theyre covering
up the conspiracy, because theres no reason to think otherwise.
This is a typical instance of our next fallacy.
Appeal to ignoranceto argue for a position by appealing to
ones lack of reasons for believing its denial.
The fallacy of appeal to ignorance has two basic formats. Here is one of them.
We dont know that statement S is false. [or]
We have no reason to think that S is false. [or]
Its not been proven that S is false. [etc.]
S is true. [or]
S is probably true.
One can go out on the limb with an appeal to ignorance and conclude that something is the case, or one can play it a bit safer and merely conclude that something is probably the case. Either, however, is fallacious.
Its surprising how often people use the appeal to ignorance. Sometimes its so
quick, its hardly noticeable:
Interviewer: And why should we hire you from among
our pool of candidates?
Interviewee: Well, why shouldnt you?
Bob: Why should we go to Shortys for lunch?
Mary: Well, why shouldnt we?
The interviewee is in essence arguing that a lack of reasons against hiring them
would itself be a reason for hiring them. Clarified like this, however, it really
does sound suspiciousand rightly so!
The other variation of the appeal to ignorance is just as popular; for example:
You havent a shred of evidence for thinking that I
cheated on this, so it must be my own work.
141
Relevance
142
Relevance
143
Relevance
I hope its clear now why the appeal to ignorance is a fallacy. From ignorance
can only flow ignorance. The only rational thing to do in a state of ignorance is
to withhold belief. If one has no reason to either believe or disbelieve something,
the only rational thing to do is to not believe.
144
Relevance
Ironically, the best person to argue against these appeals to ignorance is a fiveyear old. Have statement S be, The sum of the interior angles of a [Euclidean]
triangle equals 180 degrees. About the most a five-year-old knows about triangles is that they look a certain waypointy. Kids can use this knowledge to
distinguish triangular blocks from the square ones and the round ones. But
they certainly have no reason to believe that the sum of the interior angles of a
triangle equals 180 degrees. And now were ready for our reductio from the fiveyear-old:
I have no reason to think that the statement The sum of
the interior angles of a [Euclidean] triangle equals 180
degrees is true.
It may be false. [or]
Its possibly false.
But, of course, it is not possibly false that the sum of the interior angles of a
triangle equals 180 degreesits a necessary truth; its logically impossible for
this to be false.
Let me give you another example: You dont know anything about my father;
youre completely ignorant about him. If minimalist appeals to ignorance were
permissible, however, you could make the following inference:
I have no reason to think that Kevins father wont visit
him next weekend.
Kevins father may visit him next weekend. [or]
It is possible that he will visit Kevin next weekend.
But this just doesnt follow. Eds dead; its physically impossible for him to
visit.
Nothing follows from ones ignorancenot even knowledge about mere farflung possibilities. In a sense, you need just as much reason to believe that a
possibility exists as you need to believe that a probability exists.
Perhaps when people say For all I know, it may be so, they just mean to be
saying, For all I know, it may be so or it may not beI just dont know. If
so, then they are not arguing by appeal to ignorance. Instead, they are just
expressing their ignorance in a very misleading way.
145
Relevance
Appeal to popularity
How often have you seen something advertised as the leading brand or the
nations number one or the best selling? How often has the person taking
your order at the restaurant answered your questions about the quality of the food
by saying A lot of people order it? How often do you bump into the reply,
Oh, no, weve always done it this way! to your request for change in policy? I
would wager, a lot! These are all instances of our next fallacy:
146
Relevance
147
Relevance
The fallacy of appeal to popularity can involve a claim about what a lot of people
do currently or what a lot of people have done over timeno big difference.
Appeals to past practices:
Oh, Im afraid weve never done it that way before.
Thats just not the way we do things around here.
Its our policy to do it this way.
Its not been our policy to do it that way.
Appeals to precedent:
Weve already began doing it this way; so we
better stick with it.
We did it this way last week; if were going to
do it that way, we should have begun last week.
We allowed this last time; so we must allow it
again.
Once again, we see that informal fallacies can be very condensed and happen
very quickly. We really must be on our guard.
The appeal to precedent is especially compelling to those who think the judicial
system is a reliable indicator of whats true or right. But when an action or belief
is just plain wrong, it should be abandoned, no matter its current or past popularity. Remember: Slavery was once popular, commonly practiced, and a legal
precedent.
Appeal to force
Yeah? You got a problem with that?!
Appeal to forceto use a threat as a reason for someone to
adopt or change their beliefs, values, or intentions.
A threat is a claim that one is conditionally placing an undesirable price on someones belief, value, or intention. The classic example is If you dont give me
your wallet, Ill kill you. The mugger has put an undesirable price on your
intention to keep your wallet. The mugger certainly has not given you a reason
148
Relevance
as to why they rather than you ought to have your wallet; they have not given you
a reason to think that you are somehow the wrong person for the money and that
its been a mistake all along that youve had it instead of them. Thats why the
appeal to force is a violation of the relevance condition for cogency.
Sometimes the threats involved in the appeal to force can be quite veiled. For
example, when a boss says something like A few years ago we had an employee
that thought the same way as you dohe wasnt here long. The lone fact that
employees are getting fired for having a certain belief is no reason to think that
the belief is false.
149
Relevance
Informal Fallacies
EquivocationSupporting a conclusion by shifting from one
meaning of an ambiguous term to another.
Slippery slopeTo argue from the fact that one cannot determine
the exact boundaries of a terms extension, to the conclusion that a
quite liberal use, or even any extension, of the term is appropriate.
Appeal to false authorityWhen a statement is accepted because
it is expressed by an expert claiming to have informed,
privileged knowledge; however, one has reason to believe that the
expert is unreliable, viz., that it is quite possible that they would
express the statement even if it were not true.
Begging the questionWhen one of the premises is either a
disguised version of the conclusion or presupposes the truth of the
conclusion.
False analogyWhen there is a relevant difference between two
cases, such that what is claimed to be true of one case is no reason
to believe it is true of the other.
Straw manTo criticize or attack not someones actual argument
or conclusion or position, but rather a misrepresentation of it.
Ad hominemWhen derogatory charges are made against the
author or advocate of a position or argument, using those charges
as reasons to claim that the position is false or the argument is not
cogent.
Guilt by associationTo place an author or a position in a group
of disreputable standing. By so doing, the audience is tempted to
attribute the same disreputable characteristic to the author or
position.
Appeal to ignoranceTo argue for a position by appealing to
ones lack of reasons for believing its denial.
Appeal to popularityUsing the fact that many people believe or
value or do something as a reason to think that its correct.
Appeal to forceTo use a threat as a reason for someone to
adopt or change their beliefs, values, or intentions.
150
Relevance
151
152
Categorical logic
Everyone at the party had a good time.
No one at the party got sick.
Although, some people celebrated a bit too much.
But most people did not.
Everyone got an invitation, telling them to bring a dish
to pass. And once you know, youve got no excuse. So
no ones got any excuse for coming empty handed.
We typically talk this way. I bet you never realized that it is the language of
categorical logic.
If categorical logic is the study of deductive arguments that are made up of categorical statements, what exactly are categorical statements?
Categorical statements are statements of relations of
inclusion or exclusion between two categories of things.
OK. But now, what are categories?
Categories are classes or types or kinds of objects, events, states of affairs or
propertieskinds of things in general.
Categories can be very broad, e.g., the category of all things in the universe. Or
even broader, such as the category of all possible things in the universe, for all
timewow, thats a pile of stuff.
Categories can be much narrower too, e.g., the category of furniture. Or the category of chairs. Or of wooden chairs. Of wooden chairs sat on by you. Of
wooden chairs sat on by you on a Tuesday. With gum under them. Put there by
you [and cut that out]! A category can get so specific in its description that
nothing fits it; so the category has nothing in it; it has no members.
OK, thats what a category is. What, then, are relations of inclusion and
exclusion? Between two categories, there can be only four possible relations
of inclusion and exclusion. Lets use the symbolic categories of things that are
A and things that are B to illustrate:
All As are Bs.
No As are Bs.
Some As are Bs.
Some As are not Bs.
153
This covers all the possibilities. Lets take a closer look at each type of categorical statement and introduce some terminology and some notation.
No As are Bs.
This is the relation of total exclusionthings that are As are excluded from the
class of things that are Bs. This categorical statement is the universal negative;
again, for good reasonit is making a claim about all As, that all of them are
excluded from being Bs. Its called the E categorical statement, and its symbolized as A e B.
154
Statement
Symbol
Type
Relation
AaB
Total inclusion
No As are Bs.
AeB
Total exclusion
AiB
Partial inclusion
AoB
Partial exclusion
A Statements
Inclusive Statements
All As are Bs.
Any As are Bs.
Every A is a B.
As are all Bs.
As are always Bs.
AaB
AaB
AaB
AaB
AaB
155
Each A is a B.
Whenever something is A, its also B.
If its an A, then its a B.
An A is a B. [the is of predication]
Anything is an A unless it is a B.
A until B.
Its not an A, unless its a B.
Its not an A, without being a B.
AaB
AaB
AaB
AaB
non-B a A
non-B a A
non-B a non-A
non-B a non-A
non-A a B and A e B
non-A a B and A e B
Identity Statements
An A is identical to B.
An A is a B. [the is of identity]
A a B and B a A
A a B and B a A
There are some terms in ordinary language that you would never think of as
technical, but they very much are. The first one on our list is is.
Remember how silly it sounded when Bill Clinton, during his deposition in the
Paula Jones case, said, That depends on what the meaning of is is? Ironically, Clinton was right! Compare A Homo sapien is a mammal and A
bachelor is an unmarried male. The first is is called the is of predication.
All that is stated is that all Homo sapiens are mammals, not that all mammals are
also Homo sapiens. Whereas the second is the is of identityall bachelors are
unmarried males and all unmarried males are bachelors too. The is of predication states a single A categorical statement; the is of identity states two A
categorical statements.
The next technical term on the list is unless. If I say, The dishes are clean,
unless they were used for lunch, Im making a claim about all the dishes that
156
have not been used for lunch, viz., theyre all clean. If I tell you that the picnic is
on unless it rains, Im saying that at the time its not raining, the picnic is a still
proceeding as planned. Here, then, is a rule for how to translate the unless into
standard categorical form: The unless negates the subject of an A statement;
and the other category, then, must be the predicate.
Without often works the same way as unless: To say, One cannot graduate
without taking 128 credits, is to say that all those who do not have 128 credits
are not able to graduate. You cant make an omelet without breaking eggs,
means that all the times when youre not able to break eggs, youre not able to
make an omelet.
Only, only if, and none but are extremely tricky and important terms to
keep straight, especially around tax timeOnly those below such-and-such
income are eligible for this deduction, None but business expenses can be
deducted on this form, One is eligible for this deduction only if one paid taxes
the previous year.
The rule to follow with only, only if, and none but is that they refer to the
predicate. So, Only the strong survive, means that all those that survive must
have been strong. [It does not mean that all those that were strong survivedit
takes more than strength to surviveit takes some dumb luck too.]
The exception to this rule [as noted on our list above] is when one is talking
about categories in which there is only one member. For example, if I say that
only Bob showed up for the meeting, I mean that all people who are Bob
attended the meeting and all the people who attended the meeting are Bob. This
sounds kind of funny, but it clearly states the point, and thats the important
thing; so get used to sounding funny when putting statements into standard
categorical form.
A strange cousin to the none but is the all but. This behaves rather uniquely,
so be awareits another one of those cases in which there are two categorical
statements packed into one sentence. If I tell you that all the members except
Bob have paid their dues, Im telling you that all those other than Bob [all the
non-Bobs] have indeed paid, and Bob has notthats why all except Bob have
paid.
157
line for serious cash or serious jail time. If more people knew
their way around categorical statements, fewer people would be
heading to H&R Block every year. Sometimes, wording is
everything, and this is one of those times.
E Statements
No As are Bs.
Never are As Bs.
As are never Bs.
As are not Bs.
There isnt a single case of A that is B.
AeB
AeB
AeB
AeB
AeB
I Statements
Some As are Bs.
A few As are Bs.
At least one A is B.
There are ABs.
Frequently As are Bs.
Most As are Bs.
AiB
AiB
AiB
AiB
AiB
AiB
O Statements
Some As are not Bs.
Few As are Bs.
Seldom are As Bs.
Hardly any As are Bs.
AoB
AoB
AoB
AoB
I and O Statements
Only some As are Bs.
Only a few As are Bs.
Almost all As are Bs.
Not quite all As are Bs.
[Exactly] XX% As are Bs.
Only XX% As are Bs.
Almost no As are Bs.
A i B and A o B
A i B and A o B
A i B and A o B
A i B and A o B
A i B and A o B
A i B and A o B
A i B and A o B
158
little group, which are unique because they are two categorical statements rolled
into one phrase. Be on the lookout for these cases: What makes a statement such
as Only some As are Bs true is that indeed some As are Bs, but only some
some are not.
159
To highlight another feature of the I categorical statement, let me ask you this:
On the basis of the fact that some As are Bs, can one validly infer that some As
are not Bs?
Answer: No. And why not? Well, even though the frequent explanation for
why some As are Bs is that only some are, thats not always the case. It could
very well be that what explains the fact that some As are Bs is that all of them
are. Surely, if all existing As are Bs, then some of them are! Some dinosaurs are
extinct, arent they?! OK; so you just cant infer an O categorical statement from
its corresponding I categorical statement.
The third feature to note about I categorical statements is the tremendous loss of
information that occurs when you use them to translate ordinary language
into standard categorical form. Take the following list of statements
commonly found in ordinary language:
A few As are Bs.
At least half the As are Bs.
Most As are Bs.
Many As are Bs.
From the point of view of categorical logic, these all get translated merely as
Some As are Bs. Information about differences in the proportions of As that
are Bs is lost.
Moreover, if I were to say, Some things are As despite their being Bs,
categorical logic only picks up on the fact that some As are Bs; it totally misses
the explanatory information carried by my saying that these As are As in spite
of, not because of, their also being Bs.
There is nothing that will ever be more powerful in its capacity to carry
information than ordinary language. No language of computers, mathematics, or
logic is ever going to come up to ordinary languages potential for telling us
about the world and relaying subtle differences and details.
So why are we studying this categorical language of logic, if its so incredibly
poor at capturing the ordinary language of daily discourse and debate? Good
questionI only hope I can give you a good enough answer:
While ordinary language has the greatest capacity for conveying information,
what means does it have for assessing the validity of arguments? Well, none,
really. The only assessment tool at your disposal while using only ordinary
language is whether an argument sounds good or not. And certainly, how
someones argument sounds, how it strikes your untutored intuitions, is hardly a
reliable gauge of validity.
160
On the other hand, categorical logic will provide us with a very accessible and
reliable set of tools for assessing the validity of arguments. In order to apply
those tools to arguments we encounter in daily discourse, however, the
arguments must first be translated into standard categorical form. And then, after
the assessment of validity is made, the arguments must be translated back into
ordinary language.
As in all of life, there is a trade-off: In order to better assess the validity of our
daily arguments by means of categorical logic, we must sacrifice some
information. If were unwilling to do the latter, were unable to do the former.
161
But lets not get too set in our ways here, thinking that there is something
special about the letters A and B, and about having A always stand for the
subject and B always stand for the predicate! That couldnt be farther from the
truth and function of symbols!
What is the function of a symbol? To stand for something and help us
remember what it stands for. The moment a symbol fails to do this for you is
the moment you should ditch it. So make your symbols make sense, so that
its easy to see what they stand for. Lets discuss some examples of putting
categorical statements into notation:
Aardvarks are boisterous.
AaB
Think of your old alphabet book, as youre choosing your symbols: A is for
aardvark, with its long, ugly snout; B is for boisterous, must you shout like a
lout?
Boisterous creatures are all aardvarks.
BaA
Symbolizing this one as A a B would be asking for troublelike using the green
light to stand for Stop.
The aardvark is one ugly animal.
AaU
AaP
What better symbol is there for peed?! Even if the original sentence were,
The aardvark urinated on the rug, ours would have been a better choicewhy?
Alice peed on the rug too.
AL a P
When your first choice is already spoken for, include or move to the second
letter. If thats taken, move to the third, etc.
Slammers are slackers.
SLAM a SLAC
162
BA a AU
163
164
This is a famous quotation from John Stuart Mill. I include it to illustrate that,
like with most rules, our rule about how to handle only has exceptions. In the
case of this famous line from Mill, the only is not functioning to establish a
relation between the categories; its instead part of the description of one of the
categories. The subject of Mills categorical statement is, Those people who
know only their own side of the case. The predicate category is, Those people
who know little of their own side of the case. The claim, then, is that all those
in the first category are also in the latter: KOT a KLT.
No friend is better than a fair-weather friend.
Heres another tricky one, similar to Mills one-liner. We are accustomed to the
word no working to make the statement into an E categorical statement. But, if
we treat this no as doing this, then we would interpret the sentence as saying,
None of ones friends are any better than just fair-weather friends. [Thats
depressing, being stuck with nothing but such lousy friendships.] But thats not
what this famous one-liner is sayingwe havent captured it correctly. What
this is driving at is the having no friends at all, viz., being friendless, is actually
better than just having fair-weather friends. Notice that the no was functioning
as a nonas part of the title of the subject category: F a BFWF.
A rose by any other name would smell as sweet.
Lets put Shakespeare into standard categorical form: All roses that are named
other than rose, e.g., Jesse, are roses that smell as sweet as roses that are
named rose. From a literary point of view, this sucks. But from a logical point
of view, this is actually better, and clarifies the original sentence quite well.
Pop quiz: You cant swing a dead cat without bumping into
a categorical statement!
In fact, the preceding sentence illustrates its own point.
So if you want more practice at identifying categorical
statements in the field, just do your daily reading routine and
youll be looking at one categorical statement right after another.
Seriously! I just grabbed the closest book to me right now and
Ive randomly opened it and picked a paragraph as Im keying
this inI kid you not! The book happens to be Word 98 for
Macs for Dummies. On page 269, under the heading Installing
the miniprograms, is the following paragraph, which consists of
nothing but categorical statementssometimes packed morethan-one to a sentence. See if you can translate the paragraph
into standard categorical form.
165
This little Venn represents the entire universestrange but true. It represents all possible relations of inclusion and exclusion between the two categories, A and B.
166
Pop quiz: Where would the following things live on our Venn?
[Remember, my symbols will always make sense.]
red ants
brown ants
red cats
brown cats
167
We begin with our bare Venn on the left, and shade in the left crescent, to get
the diagram on the right. We do this because, in that crescent were any As that
were not Bs. But, A a B requires that there be no such creatures! Any As that
were in there, then, had to be made into Bs, so that all As are Bs. So we just
shoved them into B-land, and that did it.
Important tip: Think of shading as way of herding things into the right areas
so as to meet the descriptions expressed by the statement youre diagramming.
This is the only sort of counterintuitive aspect about using the Venn diagram
usually, with pie charts and bar graphs, etc., shading represents the existence
of things. But with Venns, shading represents the nonexistence of things!
A e B No As are Bs.
Here, we had to make sure that all As get evicted from B-land, so that theres
absolutely no chance for an A to be a B. Thats why we shaded the AB football,
thereby installing a complete divide between the As and the Bs.
168
Similarly, unpack the O statement, and it will tell you right where to put the
asterisk: There is at least one A and its not a Bits an A thats outside of Bland. The asterisk must stay out of B-land and yet must stay in A-land, and thats
why it plops down in the left crescent.
Pop quiz:
On the Venn below, diagram the following [dont peek at the
answers until youre done!]:
1. All Bs are As.
2. As are identical to Bs.
3. Some non-As are non-B.
169
1. B a A
2. A a B and B a A
3. A i B
4. B a A
170
5. A i B and A o B
6. A a B and A e B
So, if you know that all cats are mammals, you immediately know that its false
that some cats are not mammalsthe truth of an A statement is equivalent to the
falsity of its corresponding O statement. If you know that some students passed
171
the course, you know that its false that none of them did. These are just two
different ways of saying the same thing. And if you know that not all the food
was good, you know that some of it was not.
172
Certainly, the two statements, Some of the mail is not sorted, and All of the
mail is unsorted, are not equivalent. So, its very important to keep track of
this difference between external and internal negation.
Pop quiz:
After a century in the shadow of Newtonian ideas, according
to which light is composed of small particles, wave models of
light were revived about 1800, first by an Englishman,
Thomas Young, and then by a Frenchman, Augustin Fresnel.
Fresnels model was submitted for a prize offered by the
French Academy of Sciences. One of the judges for the
academy, S.D. Poisson, deduced that according to Fresnels
model, the shadow of a small circular disk produced by a
narrow beam of light should exhibit a bright spot right in the
center of the shadow. Poisson and the other judges are
reputed to have thought that this refuted Fresnels hypotheses
because they had never heard of there being such a
phenomenon and regarded it as highly unlikely to exist. No
known particle models predicted such a spot. But when
the experiment was carried out in carefully controlled
circumstances, there was the spot, just as required by
Fresnels model. Fresnel received the prize in 1818. [Ronald
Giere, Understanding Scientific Reasoning.]
The sentence above in bold can be constructed three ways, due
to the distinction between internal and external negation.
Find all three ways.
And which way must be true in order for the results of the
experiment to work best as evidence for Fresnels wave
theory of light and evidence against the particle theory?
BTW: Did you catch the misuse of deduced? And who really
deserved the prize here?
173
expressing categorical statements merely within the confines of standard categorical form.
Traditionally, this has come under the title of immediate inference. But that
title is a rather misleading understatement. When two statements are two ways of
saying the same thing, then of course you can infer one from the other; after all,
they are simply two ways of saying the same thing!
So, rather than calling these immediate inferences, lets call them equivalents.
Equivalent converses
There are certain classic ways of manipulating categorical statements so as to
generate new ones. We will study three different ways of generating categorical
statements, the first of which is the converse.
The converse of a categorical statement is created simply by switching the
subject and the predicate. So the converse of All members have contributed
is All the contributors are members.
The question now is, which converses are equivalent to their originals?
We will use the Venn diagram to discover and prove the equivalence or nonequivalence of categorical statements.
Weve already used the Venn to represent categorical statements and the relations between their categories. So, if we are wondering if two statements are
equivalent [namely, just two ways of saying the same thing], then, if we diagram
both of them and end up with identical diagrams, thats our proof that the
statements are equivalent.
Identical Vennsidentical statements. Different Vennsdifferent statements. Its that simple.
174
Lets begin our hunt for equivalent converses, by looking at the A statement. We
first diagram A a B. Remember, we herd all the As into B-land by means of
shading.
AaB
And now, how would you diagram the converseB a A? Youre going to herd
all the Bs into A-land. Heres a fresh Venn for you to use:
BaA
175
AaB
BaA
No, theyre not identical. So, the converse of an A statement is not equivalent to
its originalyou cant infer one on the basis of the other. Weve proven it!
Just think about it tooto say that all cats are mammals is for sure not to say that
all mammals are cats. And likewise, we cant infer that all mammals are cats
[which is flamingly false] from the statement that all cats are mammals [which is
obviously true].
Lets test the next oneis the converse of an E statement equivalent to its
original?
Begin by diagramming A e B. Rememberyou herd all the As out of B-land, in
order to get it so that not a single A can be a B:
AeB
And now, on this fresh Venn, how would you represent the converse, B e A?
176
Herding all the Bs out of A-land now, you get the following:
BeA
BeA
177
How about the I statement; is its converse equivalent to its original? Lets get
A i B represented on the Venn and see. Remember, we now shift to the asterisk
to represent the claim that at least one A is a B:
AiB
Using the same Venn this time, how would you represent the converse, B i A
that there is at least one B and its also an A?
BiA
178
AoB
And now, how would you represent B o A, [There is at least one B, and its
outside of A-land.]?
BoA
Comparing the two Venns, we see that they are Close, but no cigar!
AoB
BoA
Thinking through an example will make it obvious that conversion does not hold
for O statements: To say that some animals are not mammals is one thing; to say
that some mammals are not animals is quite another!
179
Equivalent obverses
Another way of generating categorical statements is by means of obversion.
Making the obverse of a categorical statement is a two-step process:
Obverse:
1. Change the quality of the statement. That is to
say, change it from an affirmative to a negative or
from a negative to an affirmative. So, if its an A
statement, change it to an E; if its an O
statement, change it to an I. Think of it as
changing the charge of the statement.
2. Negate the predicate.
So, the obverse of All As are Bs, is No As are non-Bs. Read through the list
and youll quickly get a feel for it:
AaB
AeB
AiB
AoB
AeB
AaB
AoB
AiB
Some obverses get a bit strange sounding, e.g., the obverse of the I statement
Some aardvarks are not other than butt ugly. With all the negatives, it gets
a little hard to follow. That will turn out to be one of the benefits of knowing the
equivalent ways of expressing categorical statementsso you can translate those
statements into more positive, understandable terms.
Lets see, then, which obverses are equivalent to their originals. Lets start with
A a B and its obverse, A e B. Heres the Venn for A a B. On the fresh Venn on
the right, diagram A e Bthat there are no As that are outside of B-land. [All
B -land, must get herded out of there and into B-land, so
those As that are in AB
that none of those As are in B-land anymore.]
180
AaB
Your verdict? You should have gotten the same Venn for both. Herding all the
As over to make Bs out of them [A a B] and herding them all over so that theyre
no longer non-Bs [A e B] results in identical Venns.
These may be different motives for shading, but thats not what matters here.
What matters is results. These are two different ways of expressing the same
statement.
So the obverse of the A statement is equivalent to its original. And, sure
enoughNo cats fail to be mammals, is just a less straightforward way of
saying All cats are mammals.
How about the obverse of the E statement; are A e B and A a B equivalent?
[Dont peek; see if you can find the answer before you scroll down.]
AeB
You should get the same diagram againA e B = A a B. We can say that no cats
are reptiles, or we could say that all cats are other than reptilesits the same
thing.
How about the obverse of the I statementare A i B and A o B equivalent?
181
AiB
Same diagram againto say that some cats are brown and to say that some cats
are not a color other than brown is to say the same thing. The latter way is just a
bit clumsier.
And lastly, what do you think about the equivalence of the O statement and its
obverse?
AoB
Yep; the same againA o B = A i B. To claim that some cats are not brown is
to claim that some cats are colored other than brown.
So add all the obverses to your list of equivalents!
Equivalent contrapositives
The contrapositive of a categorical statement is generated by a two-step process
thats sort of a hybrid of the converse and the obverse.
Contrapositive:
1. Switch the subject and the predicate.
2. Negate the subject and the predicate.
182
The mantra of contraposition is: Flip & NegateFlip & NegateFlip &
Negate.
Heres the list of contrapositives, then. Say them to yourself and get used to the
funny-sounding ones:
AaB
AeB
AiB
AoB
BaA
BeA
BiA
BoA
How about that last one! Some non-brown things are not other than alligators?!
Henry Kissinger talks like that! Mumble in a deep, gravelly voice: It is not
ruled out that I would fail to be absent at such an occasion. Hank, are you
coming or not?! And thats why we need to know our equivalents: To translate
the Henry Kissingers into ordinary language.
Lets begin with the A statement and its contrapositiveare A a B and B a A
equivalent? Shade the Venn on the right so that all the non-Bs are herded into
non-A-land.
AaB
You should be getting the same diagram as A a B. The process will be a bit
different, but the result will be the same: With A a B, you herded all the As into
B-land; with B a A, you herded all the Bs out into the big surrounding area of
AB.
So, the contrapositive of the A statement is equivalent to its originalyou can
say, All cats are mammals, or you can say, All animals other than mammals
are not cats. [Question: Before knowing what you do nowviz., that the
contrapositive of an A statement is equivalentwould you have correctly
identified these statements as saying the same thing?]
183
So, saying that no cats are reptiles and saying that no animals that arent reptiles
are not cats is to say two different things. We know this now for sure.
Before, when all we had to rely on was just our general intuitions on how these
statements sounded, I doubt if any of us could tell whether these statements were
equivalent or not.
The Venns are teaching us things already!
Next, lets test the contrapositive of the I statementA i B and B i A.
Place an asterisk on the Venn on the right to indicate that there is at least one
thing that is both a non-B and a non-A.
184
AiB
The asterisk will go in the same place as it did with A o Bits definitely a nonB, but to keep from being a non-A, it must remain in A-land.
185
Logical equivalents
Converse
Obverse
Contrapositive
Contradictories
E and I
A,E,I, and O
A and O
A and O
E and I
The truth of one =
the falsity of the other.
186
HaM
Converse
none
Obverse
HeM
Contrapositive
MaH
Contradictory
Lets play around with Those who live by the sword, die by the sword.
Original:
LaD
Converse
none
Obverse
LeD
Contrapositive
DaL
Contradictory
Another way to practice finding equivalents is to let our list take us to wherever it
leads us. This is more fun. Lets do it with L a D:
We cant take the converse of L a D, but we can always take the obversewhich
gives us L e D. And now we can take the converse of thatwhich would give
us D e L. The converse of that would give us nothing new, but the obverse does,
namely D a L . And now, how does D a L compare to our original, L a D?
Thats right; its the contrapositive. See? [FYIthe contrapositive [D a L] of
L a D is just the obverse of the converse of the obverse of L a D, all of which are
equivalentso, no wonder its equivalent!]
Practice, practice, practice: All you need is a little scratch papera gum
wrapper or a napkin will do. Lets do: Some profs are a pain in the butt.
P i PB = PB i P = PB o P = P o PB
[original => converse => obverse => contrapositive]
187
Lets play with this little gem from Socrates: The unexamined life is not worth
living.
A few new issues crop up with this example. The first issue is the question of
how to interpret the statement.
My advice is to always give the statement the most literal representation
possible, to capture all of its aspects and information.
Is Socrates making a universal claim or just a particular claim? Is he launching a
claim about all unexamined lives or just some of them? He seems to be making
a universal claim [or else his claim sort of fizzles out as a lofty pearl of wisdom,
and becomes a mere platitude]. So Socrates is making an A statement about
unexamined lives, claiming that all of them are not worthy of being lived. And
so now we are ready to put it into our notationE a W.
You may be asking why I didnt symbolize the category of unexamined lives
with U. The reason I didnt, is that then the negation [the un] would be harder
to keep track of. This is especially a problem with statements such as, The
unexamined life is uninteresting. Both categories are negative categories, and
so referring to them by means of their negative aspects wouldnt distinguish
them. A related problem crops up with, The unexamined life is one of
urgency.
My recommendation is to use the core positive aspect of a category to determine
your choice of notation. Thats why the unexamined life is best thought of as the
non-Examined life [and the uninteresting as the non-Interesting].
So lets put Socrates little observation through its paces:
We begin with E a W. We know the converse is not equivalent; so, whats the
obverse [which we can always do]? Taking the obverse of E a W brings us to
our next little issue.
When we try to negate the predicate of E a W , we get a double negationwe
would be putting a bar on top of W. When this happens, the double negations
just cancel each other outnon-non-W and W are the same. So the obverse of
E a W is E e W.
And now, with these little issues cleared up, lets follow the equivalents of E a W
to where they lead us:
EaW = EeW=WeE = WaE
[original => obverse => converse => obverse = contrapositive of the original]
188
Notice how we were able to translate Socrates famous one-liner into positive
categoriesall lives worth living are the examined ones.
189
With contraries, both statements cant be true at the same time, but both
statements can be false at the same time.
Take the statements, Kevin is bald, and Kevin is hairy. These are contraries
the predicates of baldness and hairiness are contrary predicates. Theres no
way I can be both bald and hairy at the same time. But both statements can be
false; in fact, they are false [at least for a few years yet]. Im sort of fuzzy on top.
The contradictory of bald is simply non-bald. If you want to make sure
youre stating the contradictory [the simple denial] of something, there is one
fail-safe way to do itjust slap a non or a not in front of it. So, the
contradictory of Kevin is bald, is It is not the case that Kevin is bald, or
Kevin is not bald, or Kevin is non-bald.
Confusions and misrepresentations can easily occur when one loses track of the
difference between contraries and contradictories. Heres an instance:
Take the statement, Some people are not happy with the candidates. We would
put that into standard categorical form as: P o HC. And now that we know that
the obverse is always equivalent to its original, we know P o HC is equivalent to
P i HC. But now, if we translate that back into ordinary language, we might be
tempted to express this as, Some people are unhappy with the candidates. But
that would be a mistake. Happy and unhappy are contrary predicatesone
could be neither happy nor unhappy with the candidatesone could simply be
totally blah about them. So, the proper rendering of P i H C would be, Some
people are non-happy with candidatesa klutzy phrase, but an accurate
representation of our original.
To treat contraries as if they were contradictories is the commit the fallacy of
false dichotomy. This happens so frequently that many cases have obtained the
status of slogans: e.g., If youre not part of the solution, youre part of the
problem., or Either youre for us or against us. In both of these cases, there is
a neutral positiona middle ground that is mistakenly ignored.
When trying to figure out if two statements or predicates are either contraries or
contradictories, you need to ask the following questions:
1) Can both be true simultaneously?
2) Can both be false simultaneously?
Lets go through a few examples, to get a good conceptual feel for the difference.
190
heavy
rich
near
fast
empty
loud
Contrary
Contradictory
light
poor
far
slow
full
quiet
not heavy
not rich
not near
not fast
not empty
not loud
impolite
impossible
improbable
unintelligent
inappropriate
unapproved
invalid
While were on the topic of contraries and contradictories, what are the relations
among the following, where A is an action?
The duty to do A
No duty to do A
The duty to not do A
Answer: Having the duty to do A and having no duty to do it are contradictories.
Having the duty to do A and having the duty to not do it are contraries. One
cant have a duty to do something and, in the same sense, have a duty to refrain
from doing it too. But one can have neither a duty to do something nor a duty to
refrain from doing itone is simply at liberty to do it, if one chooses. [To see
this, have the action be, e.g., eating a cheese sandwich for lunch.]
What about the relations among the following, in which p stands for any statement, e.g., Winona is in Minnesota?
191
To believe that p
To not believe that p
To believe that not p
Answer: Believing that something is the case and not believing that it is the case
are contradictory states. Believing that something is the case and believing that
it is not the case are contraries. One cant believe that Winona is in Minnesota
and believe that Winona is not in Minnesota, but one who has never heard of
Winona could easily fail to have either belief.
And now you try one:
To see that p
To not see that p
To see that not p
See a pattern? Its the distinction we discussed earlier, between internal and
external negation. The failure to properly distinguish between internal and
external negation is the source of many instances of the fallacy of false
dichotomy. For example, when one hastily thinks that someone is an atheist, on
the basis of theyre admitting that they dont believe in a God. All one can
conclude, on the basis of their admission, is that they are agnostic. If someone
doesnt believe in global warming, that doesnt imply that they believe there is no
global warming. Between the belief that p and the belief that not p is the huge
option of withholding beliefexactly what one ought to do when one lacks
sufficient evidence for believing one way or the other.
Subcontraries
A cousin of the contrary is the subcontrary. Two statements are subcontraries
when they can both be true, but they cannot both be false.
I and O categorical statements are subcontraries. Some men have big feet,
and Some men dont have big feet, can both be true [in fact, they are], but they
cannot both be false.
Pop quiz:
Why cant Some men have big feet, and Some men
dont have big feet, both be false?
192
Syllogisms
Weve studied categorical statements and the equivalent ways of expressing them
so as to make immediate inferences from one to another. So weve already
been studying various categorical arguments, albeit really short onesones with
only one premise and one conclusion. Its time to study some longer arguments,
ones with multiple premises.
The type of argument thats most frequently found in categorical form is the
syllogism. It has quite a few specifications:
Its a deductive argument, with two premises, one conclusion, all in the form of
categorical statements, concerning exactly three categories. Lets list all these
features, so we can keep track of them better:
Syllogism:
Deductive argument
2 premises
1 conclusion
Categorical statements
3 categories
Syllogisms have so many specs that youd think theyd be quite rare, but theyre
not. Heres a typical example:
People who know the proper rules of punctuation and grammar
do well on the composition part of the Law School Aptitude
Test. Which is why I think Mary doesnt know her way around
grammar and punctuation very wellshe bombed the comp part
of the LSAT.
The basic format of the syllogism looks like this, once symbolized in our
notation:
AvB
BvC
AvC
193
Its easy to distill the argument above into this format. The first premise, in
standard categorical form, is the A statement that all people who know the proper
rules of grammar and punctuation do well on the LSAT. The second premise is
the last clause of the passage: The E statement that no one who is Mary did well
on the LSAT [in fact, she did poorly, but we dont need that information to infer
the conclusion]. And the conclusion is the E statement that Mary doesnt know
proper grammar and punctuation. Choosing our symbols wisely, we would put
this into our notation as:
KaW
MeW
MeK
Note how efficient our notation is: We can distill our argument down to
thisnine measly letters. Thats amazing! The power and efficiency of our
notation will enable you to record an argument as fast as one of those court
stenographers. As fast as a presenter can be throwing an argument at you, you
can be jotting it down in the margins of your program, or some other scrap of
paper [or on your palm or Palm!], so you can quickly assess it for validity. Pretty
nifty tool, I must say.
194
The three-circled Venn will serve as our canvas. It represents the entire universe
and everything in it, with respect to being included in or excluded from categories A, B, and C.
For example, where are those things which are A and B and C? They are right in
the center of the Venn, where all three circles overlapABC.
Where are those things which are A and B, but not C? They will be in the
overlap of the A and B circles, but in the upper half of that footballABC.
Where are the things that are C but not A and not B either? Well, they are found
in the C circle, but in an area of that circle that doesnt overlap with the A circle
and doesnt overlap with the B circle. So theyre found in the odd looking area
labeled ABCthe lower-most half-circle that looks as if someone sat on it.
AaB
To indicate that all As are Bs, we use shading, as usual. We have to herd all the
As into B-land, and we find that As can come in two varietiesthose that are
also Cs and those that are non-Cs. No matter; we have to make all those As into
Bs whether they are Cs or not. [Its sort of as if the C circle isnt there.]
[You probably noticed that I started using a trimmed-down version of the Venn
as our bare canvasone without the ABC area. We arent forgetting about those
things that are ABC; were just making it a bit easier on ourselves, working with
a cleaner-looking Venn.]
195
AeB
To represent the claim that no As are Bs, you have to shade all the As out of Bland, whether those As are Cs or not. [Again, its as if the C circle isnt really
there.]
AiB
To diagram an I statement, we use an asterisk. Here, the third circle does make a
difference thats important never to forget.
We must represent the claim that there is at least one A, and that A is also a B.
We know already that the asterisk will be going in the AB overlap, but exactly
where? If we put it in the top half of the AB football, then we are specifying that
the A that is a B is definitely not a C. Was that stated in the original claim,
A i B? No! If we put the asterisk in the bottom half of the AB football, then we
are specifying that the AB is also a C. And was that stated in the original claim?
No! We are told only that the thing is an AB; we are told nothing about the
things C-ness. To indicate that it is yet undetermined whether this AB is a C or
not, you put the asterisk on the fence.
196
Your job is to capture all the information in the statement, when you diagram it,
but not read anything into it. Which is what youd be doing if you put the
asterisk above or below the C fence.
AoB
To indicate that there is at least one A that is not a B, just think about all of the
specifications in the statement and it will tell you exactly where to drop the
asterisk: The thing is an A, so itll be in the A circle, but it is also outside the B
circle. Its not stated whether the thing is a C or not, so it must be placed on the
C fence. And there you are!
Representing arguments
Were ready to begin working with syllogisms! Lets begin with perhaps the
most famous little syllogism of all:
Socrates is a man.
All men are mortal.
Socrates is mortal.
The first thing to do is to symbolize it, using our notation:
SaM
M a Mo
S a Mo
This establishes the labels for the Venn [note that weve cleaned up the Venn a
bit more, by moving the labels outside the circlesbut each of the eight areas
still retains its unique specifications]:
197
And now were ready to diagram the premises on the Vennlets do the first
premise firstS a M:
After herding Socrates into the circle of men, we next diagram the second
premise, that all men are mortalM a Mo. Herd all men to their death in Moland.
We have both premises diagrammed on the Venn now. How can we tell if the
argument is valid?
Well, keep in mind what the groundedness condition of validity is all about.
Validity is the relation between premises and conclusion such that given the
premises are true, the conclusion must be true. Given the premises hold, the
conclusion must hold too. So, given that we have accurately diagrammed the
198
premises on the Venn, we ought to be able to read the conclusion right off the
Venn, if the argument is valid.
Can we read the conclusion off the Venn; is the area representing Socrates forced
into the area of mortal things? Indeed it is! Where is Socrates? The area of
things that are S suffered a huge loss of real estatethe premises herded all of
the S area into just the innermost triangle, totally within Mo-land.
And thats how the Venn is used to test the validity of arguments: If the argument is valid, the premises force the conclusion to be true; you will be able to
read the conclusion right off the diagram. If you cant read the conclusion
off the diagram, its not valid. Its that simple.
199
CaO
OeT
CeT
Diagram the first premiseC a O [try not to peek]:
200
Now, can you read the conclusionC e Tright off the diagram? The diagram
must make it the case that not a single C can be in T-landdoes it?
Yes! All thats left of C-world is the little iron-shaped area up top. C-world is
totally cut off from T-landtheres just no way a C could possibly be a T.
So the argument is valid.
RiC
CiD
RiD
[Make sure youre able to explain exactly why the asterisk was placed just so.]
201
And now, can you read the conclusionR i Doff the diagram? Is there an
asterisk that fits the exact specifications of the conclusion? The conclusion
requires that there be something that is definitely an R and definitely a D. Is
there?
Well, the first asterisk we drew is definitely an R, but its not definitely a D. The
second asterisk we drew is definitely a D, but its not definitely an R. So we
cant read the conclusion off the diagram; its not a valid argument.
202
RiC
RiC
CaD
Beware: Even though the Venn showed us how to correct our syllogism so as to
make it into a valid one, it may not be wise to make that correction. Think again
about the new second premise which is necessary to make the argument valid
C a D. What statement would that represent? All Catholics are Democrats.
203
But that premise is just plain false! Here, the price of having a valid argument
would be to flunk miserably the acceptability condition. There is just no hope for
this argument with respect to cogency.
But often, the change in premises [or perhaps conclusion] suggested by the Venn
is quite acceptable. This, then, makes the Venn more than just a validity
gaugeit makes the Venn a wonderful diagnostic tool.
204
Is the argument validi.e., can you read the conclusion off the diagramE o I?
Answer: Not exactly. The conclusion states that there exists at least one E that
is not an I. An O statement such as this requires an asterisk to represent it, and
the premises have placed no asterisk on the Venn.
We mentioned early in our discussions of the A and the E categorical statements
that they involve no commitment to the existence of even a single member in
their subject categories. [This was important for our ability to make universal
claims about hypothetical things.] And now we have a syllogism with two universal premises and a particular conclusionan I or an O statement.
In this situation, however, to call the argument invalid because its premises did
not place the necessary asterisk on the Venn, is merely to catch the argument on a
technicality instead of really putting the argument to the test.
When you are testing the validity of a syllogism like thisone with universal
premises and a particular conclusionyou should further investigate whether
it is valid given the obvious existence of at least one member in one of its
categories.
Let me show you what I mean.
LeI
LaE
EoI
The subject of the first premise is lawyerswould you grant me the existence of
at least one lawyer? Sure! After the O.J. Simpson trial, youd probably grant me
the existence of too damn many lawyers! [Youd probably grant me the existence of at least one illiterate person and at least one educated person too, but
lets work with our obviously existing lawyer.]
205
Knowing nothing else about that lawyer, where would they live on our Venn?
[This is a tricky one.]
The lawyer sort of shinnied down the E fence, as they got knocked off the I
fence.
Next, diagram the second premiseL a E:
206
And now, can you read the conclusion off the diagram, after the shading knocks
the lawyer off the E fence too? You bet!
So, the proper, robust answer in this case is that the argument is valid, given
the obvious existence of a lawyer.
When you have a syllogism with universal premises and a particular conclusion, dont just sneak by on a technicality and call it invalid. You must
test it further to see if it is valid given the known existence of at least one
member in any one of its categories. This is called existential import. This
investigation can get a bit involved, but thats what it will take to give the
argument its day in court.
207
208
Answers:
1. Invalid
2. Invalid
3. Valid
[Tip: When choosing titles for categories, first
take a birds-eye view of the whole argument, to
see what the general topics are. Thats why I
picked shelf life rather that stored or stocked
for many weeks. Also, foods would not a
good choice, since all three of the categories are
foodsfoods with a shelf life, foods with
additives, and foods that are harmful to health.]
209
4. Invalid
5. Invalid
6. Invalid
7. Valid
210
8. Invalid
211
Be able to use your thesaurus of equivalents like this, to reduce the categories
down to the requisite three, so that the syllogism is ready for testing on the Venn.
212
213
Enthymemes
An enthymeme is a syllogism with a portion left unstated.
Usually whats left implicit is a premise:
In order to graduate, one needs to meet the residency
requirement; so it looks as though Bobs not going to be
graduating this semester.
But sometimes, the conclusion is left implicit:
In order to graduate, one needs to meet the residency
requirement. And Bobs just transferred in. So there you are.
And sometimes, the context of the discussion may even allow one to simply
make a statement and have it function as a conclusion of two implicit premises
already established earlier in the discussion. For example, in the context of
reading the residency requirement and discussing how Bob just transferred, one
could simply turn to poor Bob and say, Looks like youre outta luck, guy.
Even just a sympathetic look towards Bob would qualify as your conclusion in
this context.
As youve probably figured out by now, most of our syllogisms are
enthymemes. But then this should come as no surprise. When we were discussing the anatomy of an argument, much earlier in this etext, we saw how arguments often have implicit premises or conclusions. Syllogisms would be no
different.
We should actually be thankful that people use enthymemes so regularly. If they
didnt, their arguments would be very repetitive and much longer. We would
soon be bored and insulted by having everything explicitly stated for us.
The other virtue of using enthymemes is that it gets the audience more involved
in the argument. As they are following the argument, they must think of and fill
in the missing part[s], thereby understanding and remembering the argument
betterone hopes.
These are the beneficial uses of enthymemes. But, of course, there are abuses of
them also.
If someone has an unacceptable premise, they may want to keep it from view so
that their audience doesnt notice it. Or, if their conclusion doesnt actually
214
follow from their premises, they may try to make it appear as if it does by simply
saying, And the implication is obvious.
And thats why its a good idea to keep a critical eye on enthymemes, and test
them for validity in exactly the same way you would a full-blown syllogism.
In fact, when you test an enthymeme for validity, you must make it into a
full-blown syllogism, by making all the implicit parts explicit. This will not
only permit you to properly test it for validity, it will also help you verify that the
syllogism meets the other ARG conditions.
Lets take a look at some typical enthymemes.
1. The presidency was stressful for Clinton. Look at
how much grayer he was at the end of his two terms.
2. Of course abortion is immoral; it results in the killing
of a fetus.
3. Dr. Kevs CT software is effective. Even Karl
Kartoffelkopf passed the Critical Thinking course
using it.
Lets test the first one for validity. It leads off with the conclusion and then gives
us a reason to believe it. So a premise is left implicit: All those whose hair turns
that much grayer have experienced stressful times. Putting brackets around the
implicit parts of our enthymeme, we can then represent the entire syllogism as
follows:
CaG
[G a S]
CaS
And now its ready for diagramming on a Venn, to see if its valid. [Ill leave
that to you.]
Lets do the second one. It too leads off with the conclusion and then supplies a
premise. The implicit premise seems to be that all cases of killing the fetus are
immoral. [How well does this implicit premise do on the acceptability
condition?!]
AaK
[K a I]
AaI
215
The third example leads with the conclusion too and provides a single premise.
The implicit premise states that whatever enables Karl to pass is effective.
CTS a KP
[KP a E]
CTS a E
A special note about this one: There is a strong temptation to symbolize Even
Karl Kartoffelkopf passed the Critical Thinking course using it, as All those
who are Karl Kartoffelkopf are among those who passed the Critical Thinking
course. But look where that interpretation would leave us:
KK a PCT
________
CTS a E
We would then have four categoriesone over the limit!and we havent even
found the implicit premise yet! When this happens, its pretty good evidence that
weve misidentified the categories involved in the syllogismweve erroneously
busted up one of the categories into two. And thats exactly what we didwe
busted the predicate category of things that enable Karl Kartoffelkopf to pass,
into two categories: people who are Karl Kartoffelkopf and people able to pass
Critical Thinking. The moral of the story: Keep a birds-eye view of the whole
syllogism, to best identify its three categories.
Do you notice what all three of our examples have in common? They all have
the same formthey are all instances of Barbara, just like that famous syllogism
about Socrates being mortal. As I mentioned before, this is the most popular
and easily understood syllogism type, so its a natural to be stated as an enthymeme. [BTW: The previous sentence was self-illustrating.]
Lets do another enthymeme:
Lawyers frequently undermine the law; because anyone who
ignores the truth in order to get an acquittal undermines the law.
Once we supply the missing premise, that some lawyers ignore the truth in order
to get their clients acquitted, we can see that this syllogism has a different form
than our old friend Barbara:
IaU
[L i I]
LiU
216
We need to be able to read off the diagram that there exists at least one lawyer
that is undermining the law. We can then see that if there is a lawyer that ignores
the truth in order to get an acquittal [see the next Venn below], then that lawyer
would be forced by the first premise to undermine the law [see the second
Venn below].
217
218
Is it valid?
Answer: No! B is not guaranteed by the premises to be an R. Just as not all
syllogisms are valid, not all enthymemes are valid.
Some logic instructors will tell you that you are permitted to ascribe missing
premises only when those premises make the syllogism valid. This policy just
wont work though. There are just too many invalid enthymemes around, and
you have to be able to make sense of them and fully appreciate why theyre
invalid. So here is the best rule to follow:
When possible, attribute the author of an argument with the
implicit premise or conclusion that makes their syllogism
valid. But, if it is pretty obvious what their implicit premise
or conclusion is, you may rightfully attribute it to the author
despite the fact that it will make their syllogism invalid.
We want to be charitable readers, helping others to construct valid syllogisms
whenever possible. But sometimes it simply isnt possible, and theres a limit to
our charity.
OK, heres a last one for you:
Everyone there enjoyed the evening very much. So there were
some people who didnt enjoy the evening.
Whats the missing premise, and is the resultant syllogism valid?
Answer: The missing premise is that some people were not there. With that as
the missing premise, the syllogism could be represented and diagrammed as
follows.
TaE
[P o T]
PoE
219
We are unable to read the conclusion off the diagramthe asterisk would have
to be placed outside of E-land by the premises; just sitting on the E fence wont
do. So heres another example of an invalid enthymeme.
Pop quiz: With the help of the Venn above, what change in the
first premise would make the syllogism valid? But would the
necessary change be at the expense of one of the other ARG
conditions?
220
221
222
is the claim that at least one of the things that exist is investors decreasing confidence.
>O a <IC
E i >O
E i <IC
Now we finally have a syllogism, and a valid one at that. [Which I leave to you
to prove by means of a Venn, if you dont believe me.]
For categorical logic to have that much difficulty dealing with such an obvious
argument reveals a serious limitation of categorical logic. There must be an
easier way to handle such a simple argument, instead of using goofy catch-all
categories such as E. And indeed there is. In this chapter, we will study a system
of logic that can easily and efficiently represent our argument in the following
way:
>O <IC
>O
<IC
This system of logic is call propositional logic, and it will provide us with a
means of assessing the validity of arguments, just as did categorical logic.
Heres another case that categorical logic would find a challenge, to say the least:
If X is necessary for Y, then Z, but only if if A then B.
Put that in standard categorical form. And, of course, you cantits three
categories over the limit. And yet many statements are like this, especially
statements expressing bureaucratic rules and regulationsjust think about those
elaborate, contorted rules in the IRS Tax Code! If you want to appeal to one of
those rules to argue for a tax deduction, you better make it a valid argument, or
there may be penalties and interest to pay.
Categorical logic cant accommodate this case above, but propositional logic can.
We could easily symbolize the statement in this way:
[(YX)Z](AB)
This may look like symbol salad right now, but by the time were done studying
propositional logic, this will be perfectly intelligible, and
If X is necessary for Y, then Z, but only if if A then B,
223
224
Well:
Atomic propositions bond by means of logical
connectives to form molecular propositions.
Molecular propositions bond by means of logical
connectives to form even more complex molecular
propositions.
Molecular propositions are used as premises and
conclusions to form arguments.
Negation
For any proposition, p, there is the negation of that propositionnot p. So, if we
begin with the proposition, It snowed four inches last night, its negation is the
proposition It is not the case that it snowed four inches last night.
The symbol most often used to stand for negation is the tilde: ~. So, for every
proposition p there is its negation, ~p.
There are numerous ways of negating propositions in ordinary language. The
sure way was illustrated above: It is not the case that p. Here are a few more
ways, which should help you to extrapolate to any others you may encounter:
Its false that p.
Its not true that p.
Its wrong to think that p.
Its impossible that p.
Its not a fact that p.
Its other than that p.
It fails to be the case that p.
I deny that p.
Its rather strange to call the tilde a connective; it just hangs on an atomic
proposition and doesnt bind it in any way to another proposition. But, lets just
go along with the convention on this one, and classify it as a connective and
classify ~p as a molecular proposition.
225
Conjunction
Take the proposition, I went to Seattle, and I had a great time. This proposition
more intuitively lives up to its label as a molecular proposition. It has a
connective [and] that we would comfortably consider to be a paradigm example of a connective, binding together two atomic propositions.
Ill use the letters p and q to stand for our generic atomic propositions, and Ill
use the dot to symbolize andp q. BTW: The ampersand [&] is also used to
symbolize and.
The propositions making up the conjunction are called conjuncts.
There are many ways of saying and in ordinary language; here is just a sample
of them:
p but q
p although q
p even though q
p however q
p in spite of q
p despite q
p yet q
p notwithstanding that q
p whereas q
both p and q
p besides q
p as well as q
p and then q
p albeit q
p at the same time q
p but also q
p furthermore q
p moreover q
not only p but q
p regardless of q
p while q
p nevertheless q
p in as much as q
p in addition to q
Remember when we were talking about how there can be a huge loss of information when we move from ordinary language to the language of categorical logic,
e.g., when you have to settle for saying that some As are Bs, when the original
claim said that most As are Bs? Well, the same holds true with respect to our
attempts to take statements from ordinary language and represent them in
propositional logic.
Compare the statements p despite q and p nevertheless q. The first statement
would indicate that q was a bit of a hurdle to ps being true, while the second
statement would indicate just the reverse. And yet, both get rendered as only
p q when put in standard propositional form. Much information is lost.
226
Similarly with the statements p and then q and q and then p. They could
both be represented as p q or q p. The temporal order stated in the original
sentences is lost.
Once again we are reminded that no language of logic will ever approach
ordinary languages ability to convey information. But then we must also
remember that the ability of ordinary language to assess the validity of arguments
is pathetic. And thats why were studying how to translate arguments from
ordinary language into propositional logic, to assess their validity, and then
translate them back into ordinary language againfast and reliably.
Disjunction
This molecular proposition is built using the connective or, as in Quiet down
or Ill call the manager and Im going to Chicago or Milwaukee next
weekend. Here are a few ways of stating a disjunction:
either p or q
p or else q
alternatively p and q
p otherwise q
The symbol standardly used for or is the wedgep v q.
The propositions making up the disjunction are called disjuncts.
Conditional
The conditional statement has the form, If p then q: If you get your report in on
time, you will get a bonus, or If you dont get your report in on time, you will
be fired. And now you see why conditionals are so important!
The symbol we will be using to represent the conditional relation is the
horseshoe. So, If p then q, gets symbolized as p q. FYI: Sometimes, an
arrow [>] is used instead of the horseshoe, to represent the conditional.
The propositions making up the conditional get their own separate names: The
proposition after the if is the antecedent, and the proposition after the then is the
consequent.
Theres a bundle of ways to state the conditional relation in ordinary language. If
you just browse among various directions, contracts, laws, rules, and regulations,
youll run into many of them. [BTW: Many of my students have told me that
227
after studying this chapter, they were able to do their taxes much more easily.
Sorry, I still have no advice for making it easier to write the IRS checks.] Here,
then, is a sample of how diversely youll find the conditional, if p then q, stated:
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
p q or q p
p q or q p
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
pq
~qp
~qp
~q~p
~q~p
when p, q
q, if p
q, given p
q provided that p
p, only on condition that q
p, only because q
p only if q
none but those that are q are p
q is a necessary condition for p
p is contingent upon q
p is a sufficient condition for q
q, on condition that p
q is conditional upon p
all times that p are times that q
q, whenever p
in so far as p, it follows that q
q, so long as p
q follows from p
q is entailed by p
q, to the extent that p
q, in order that p
p implies q
p is q
p requires that q
from p, it follows that q
p means that q
q, assuming p
p, unless q
p, except on condition that q
not p, unless q
not p, without q
Find some exemplary conditionals youre comfortable with, e.g: If its a cat, its
a mammal. Run your examples through the list above, to get familiar with all
these ways of expressing the conditional.
One of the most important ways of characterizing the conditional is in terms of
necessary or sufficient conditions: The antecedent is a sufficient condition
for the consequent, while the consequent is a necessary condition for the
antecedent. This may sound like gibberish right now; but it soon wont, as you
228
think it through a bit and get a feel for the conditional relation: If p, then q must
be the case too, and ps being the case is all it takes for q to be the case.
Note that the statements, q is conditional upon p, and q, on condition that p,
are ambiguousone cannot tell, out of context, whether p is a sufficient
condition for q or a necessary condition for q.
A few of the phrases in the list above should ring a bell based on your knowledge
of the various ways of stating the A categorical statement in ordinary language.
In fact, the A statement and the conditional are two ways expressing the same
relation. With this in mind, the conditional should be easier to understand: The
subject of the A statement is the antecedent of the conditional; and the predicate
of the A statement is now the consequent of the conditional. And now you know
exactly which conditional statement is being expressed by means of only, only
if, only because, and none but. They all refer to the consequent, just as in
A categorical statements, when they all referred to the predicate.
Another popular way of expressing a conditional is with the word unless. Look
at the last four entries on the list above and see if you can formulate a rule about
how to put unless into standard propositional form.
The rule is: Remove unless and insert If not. Unless negates the antecedent,
so the rest of the sentence must be the consequent. [Without works the same
way in this context; e.g., I wont go without a fight is the same as saying If no
one puts up a fight, I wont go.]
Equivalence
For example, Being a leap year is equivalent to being a calendar year in which
February has 29 days, instead of 28. The equivalence relation is also called the
biconditional. The most frequent way of expressing it is p if and only if
qIts a leap year if and only if February has 29 days.
We will be using the triple bar to represent the statement that two propositions
are equivalent: p q.
FYI: Some people use the double arrow [<>] instead of the triple bar to
symbolize the biconditional. And logicians have actually coined a new word,
iff, to stand for if and only if.
Here, then, are some of the ways of stating the equivalence relation:
229
Neither p nor q
To say Neither p nor q is to say, Its not the case that either p or q. Its a way
of negating the disjunction. And, if its not the case that either p or q, then p
must not be the case and q must not be the case. Thats why neither p nor q gets
expressed in both of the following ways:
~(pvq)
~p~q
230
Group picture
Here then is the complete line-up of our connectives for propositional logicor
prop logic, as its called for short.
~p
pq
pvq
pq
pq
Truth
Weve studied how to build molecular propositions, using atomic propositions
and our basic connectives. Now lets look at how the truth and falsity of those
molecular propositions are determined.
Prop logic also goes by the name of truth-functional logic. And for good
reason, as we will soon see.
231
232
~p
F
T
q
T
F
T
F
pq
T
F
F
F
The first two columns of the truth table list all the possible truth values for
atomic propositions p and q. Because we now have two atomic propositions,
there are more possible ways for the two to be true or falsethey both could be
true, one could be true while the other is false, one false while the other is true, or
they both could be false. The third column details the truth value of p q in each
of these four cases.
Basically, the truth table just lays out what and means. Just think about it:
Under what circumstances is it true that Im in Chicago and having fun? When
Im in Chicago but having a lousy time? No. When Im in Minneapolis having
fun? No. When Im in Minneapolis having a lousy time? No! Only when Im
both in Chicago and having fun. A conjunction is true only when both of its
conjuncts are true.
Nextdisjunction.
233
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
pvq
T
T
T
F
pq
T
F
T
T
q
T
F
T
F
Whoa! That seems strangehow can a conditional be true when its atomic parts
are all false?! Usually this is chalked up to being a peculiarity of the material
conditional, as logicians call it. But that is not a very satisfactory answer. Let
me at least try to make some sense of our truth tables analysis of the conditional.
Think of the conditional as being like a promise. Lets say I promise you that
if it rains, Ill have my umbrella. Have I come through on my promise on a rainy
day that I have my umbrella with me [the first row of the truth table]? Sure.
How about the day that its raining and I dont have my umbrella [the second
row]? No; Ive broken my promisemy conditional statement is falsified. How
about those days that it is not raining? How about when I have my umbrella with
me on a sunny day [because I always have my umbrella in my pack]? I sure
havent broken my promise, have I? And, have I made a false promise when I
decide to leave my umbrella home on a perfectly sunny day? No. On those days
when it is not raining, my promise to have my umbrella when its raining goes
untested, but my promise is still alive and wellits still a true promise.
And so it is with the conditionalit is false only when its antecedent is true
and its consequent is false. The rest of the time it is true, if only by virtue of
being untested.
234
p q
T
F
F
T
q
T
F
T
F
235
Thats one of the many uses of the truth table. So lets try it. When is the
following proposition true and when is it false?
(p q) (q p)
Lets build a truth table for this proposition. The columns of the truth table, in a
sense, record how the proposition was constructed. This proposition began with
the atomic propositions p and q. The first molecular proposition built up was
p q. The second molecular proposition was q p. And then these two
propositions were conjoined to form the final product, (p q) (q p).
This process of construction goes on the top of our truth table:
p
pq
qp
(p q) (q p)
We next record, in the first two columns, all the possible ways that the atomic
propositions can be true or false, just as we did before when we gave the truth
tables that truth-functionally defined the connectives:
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
pq
qp
(p q) (q p)
And then we record how those truth values determine the truth values of our
molecular propositionsfirst the two conditionals and then the final conjunction:
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
pq
T
F
T
T
qp
T
T
F
T
(p q) (q p)
T
F
F
T
[That fourth column, for q p, might be faking you out: In the first row, when q
is T and p is T, q p is T, and in the second row, when q is F and p is T, q p is
T, but in the third row, when q is T and p is F, q p is finally F, and so on.]
236
q
T
F
T
F
pq
T
F
T
T
qp
T
T
F
T
(p q) (q p)
T
F
F
T
p q
T
F
F
T
And now we see why the equivalence relation is also called the biconditional,
and why p if and only if q is a frequent way of expressing the triple bar: p q
is equivalent to the conjunction of p q and its converse.
[Yes, indeed, you are familiar with that notion from categorical logic. Mini pop
quiz: whats the contrapositive of p q?]
Lets do another one: Under what circumstances is it true that ~(p ~q)?
First we must figure out how many rows the truth table will have. You
probably think it will have four, and youre right. Heres how to calculate
exactly how many rows your truth table will have, for any proposition youre
working with:
Rows = 2
237
~q
p ~q
~(p ~q)
q
T
F
T
F
~q
p ~q
~(p ~q)
Then, make your truth-value assignments for the other molecular propositions,
based on the truth values you have already assigned and what the connectives are
for those molecular propositions. So, when q is T, ~q is F, and when q is F, ~q is
T, etc. And for p ~q, when p is T and ~q is F, then p ~q will be F, etc. Here is
where you must know how the connectives determine truth valueswork on this
until you dont even have to think about it anymore. Your truth table will then
look as follows.
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
~q
F
T
F
T
p ~q
F
T
F
F
~(p ~q)
T
F
T
T
And these, then, are the circumstances under which ~(p ~q) is true and the one
circumstance under which it is false.
Where have you seen this column of truth values before? Thats right: Its
identical to the column for the conditional, p q. In a sense, what ~(p ~q) is
claiming is that it will not be the case that [the antecedent] p is true while [the
238
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
~q
F
T
F
T
p ~q
F
T
F
F
~(p ~q)
T
F
T
T
pq
T
F
T
T
Proving equivalence
We have twice illustrated another use of the truth table: To prove that two
propositions are equivalent, i.e., just two ways of saying the same thing. If their
two columns of the truth table are identical, they are equivalent. That, after all,
was the truth-functional definition of equivalence: That the propositions have the
same truth values in all possible circumstances.
Remember how we proved two statements were equivalent in categorical logic?
We showed they had identical Venn diagrams. Well, similarly for proving equivalence in prop logic, only now our medium of proof is the truth table instead of
the Venn.
So: Identical columns; identical propositions.
239
p
T
T
T
T
F
F
F
F
q
T
T
F
F
T
T
F
F
r
T
F
T
F
T
F
T
F
pq
T
T
F
F
F
F
F
F
(p q) r
T
F
T
T
T
T
T
T
Soup or salad
You are reading a menu in a restaurant, and it says that with the entrees, You
may have soup or salad. Youve done a great job of learning the truthfunctional definitions of the connectives, and you now think to yourself, A
disjunction is false only under one case, viz., when both disjuncts are false;
otherwise its true. With this fresh in your mind, you tell the person taking your
order that youd like soup and salad [both disjuncts] with your entree. The
person is not impressed and promptly sets you straight on the real meaning of the
phrase. Which is?
You may have soup or salad, but not both. That is to say, You may have
soup or salad, but not the conjunction of soup and salad. We are now ready to
put our proposition into notation. Since the first letter of both atomic propositions is s, lets pick other letters for our symbol choice: (U v A) ~(U A).
Do the truth table for this and show how your server was correct [you were just
being a jerk]. How many rows and how many columns? [Dont look down!]
240
A
T
F
T
F
UvA
T
T
T
F
UA
T
F
F
F
~(U A)
F
T
T
T
(U v A) ~(U A)
F
T
T
F
q
T
F
T
F
pVq
F
T
T
F
241
I mentioned before that the truth table can ironically tell you when a proposition
is true and when its false even if you dont know what the proposition means.
Well, the truth table can also tell you if the proposition is inconsistent or not even
if you dont know what it means. To be inconsistent is to be self-contradictory.
To be self-contradictory is to be logically impossible. It is to be necessarily
falsefalse in all possible cases. And how is that expressed on the truth table?
With a column of Fs. Let me illustrate with a simple example: p ~p. This is
the most blatantly inconsistent statement.
p
T
F
~p
F
T
p ~p
F
F
~p
F
T
p ~p
F
F
~(p ~p)
T
T
[So the proposition that states that a contradiction doesnt happen, is necessarily
true.]
As an example of a contingent proposition, viz., a proposition that is true under
some possible circumstances and false under some, you can pick your favorite
truth-functional definition of a connective. Lets pick the conditional:
p
T
T
F
F
pq
T
F
T
T
q
T
F
T
F
242
Disambiguating this collection of squiggles finally makes it into either a conditional or a conjunction. We use parentheses to make it either a conditional or a
conjunctionwe establish the main connective. So, we could make p q r
into a conditional(p q) ror into a conjunctionp (q r).
Note the difference between these two:
(p q) r
p (q r)
The first states that If p and q, then r; the second states that p and if q then r.
Lets try another one. Whats the main connective?
~p v q r
Wow, this is really ambiguous! This could be a conditional, or a disjunction,
or it could even be the case that the tilde is the main connective. Here are all the
ways to make propositions out of the mess above:
1. (~p v q) r
2. ~(p v q) r
3. ~p v (q r)
4. ~[(p v q) r]
5. ~[p v (q r)]
And heres how you would say these propositionsnote their differences:
1. If either not p or else q, then r.
2. If its not the case that either p or q, then r.
3. Either not p or if q then r.
4. Its not the case that if either p or q then r.
5. Its not the case that either p or if q then r.
243
Can you tell the differences among these? If you cant, you dont have to take
my word for it that theyre different. You can tell for yourself whether Im right
or wrong, simply by doing what? Thats right, just by doing truth tables for
them.
FYI: If you run into such a complicated molecular proposition that you need yet
another means for disambiguating it, besides the parentheses and the square
brackets, you have my sympathy and you have what are called braces{ }.
Wed need them if we wanted to deny that beefy proposition I used at the
beginning of this chapter:
~{[ ( Y X ) Z ] ( A B )}
Compare this to:
~[ ( Y X ) Z ] ( A B )
Propositional arguments
Weve studied how to build propositions and how to find out under what
circumstances they are true or false.
Now its time to build arguments out of those propositions and find out if those
arguments are valid or invalid.
As youve probably guessed by now: We will use the truth table for this too.
[It slices, it dices, its ten utensils in one!]
To see why the truth table is such an excellent tool to use for testing validity,
lets just refresh our memories again on what validity is. Think back
244
pq
T
F
T
T
q
T
F
T
F
C
q
T
F
T
F
P1
pq
T
F
T
T
Is there any row in which the premises are true while the conclusion is false?
No.
If you cant find a row on the truth table in which the premises are true
while the conclusion is false, the argument is valid.
So this is a valid argument:
pq
p
q
245
Moreover, any argument with this form will be valid too. Weve proven it by
means of the truth table.
This argument form is historically called Modus Ponens. But, to help us
remember the name of this argument form, lets rename it by what it does. [Like
giving a nickname to someone. For example, Ill never forget who Booger was,
and what he did.] What would be a good name for this argument?
pq
p
q
Well, its second premise is doing what to the first premise? Its affirming the
antecedent of that first premise. [You were about to say that, right?] This name
tells you exactly what the argument looks like: Since the only proposition with
an antecedent is a conditional, the first premise must be a conditional, and the
second premise is the antecedent of that conditional, and the conclusion is whats
left over.
Now that we have proven that Affirming the Antecedent is a valid argument
form, you can prove that an argument is valid simply by correctly citing it as
an instance of Affirming the Antecedent.
This is handy: You can now use the argument form as a template for spotting
one type of valid argument. In fact, Affirming the Antecedent is probably the
most frequently used propositional argument. In fact, the argument we used to
kick off this chapter was an instance of Affirming the Antecedent:
1. If oil prices continue to increase, investor confidence
will decrease.
2. Oil prices will continue to increase.
3. Investor confidence will decrease.
>O <IC
>O
<IC
Lets try testing the validity of another argument, using the truth table:
pq
q
p
This should be pretty easy, since this argument is made up of the same propositions, so we can use the same truth tablewe only need to relabel its columns:
246
C
p
T
T
F
F
P2
q
T
F
T
F
P1
pq
T
F
T
T
And now we can ask the magic question: Is there any row in which the
premises are true while the conclusion is false? Yes there isthe third row of
truth-value assignments details exactly that case.
Such a row is called a counterexample. It proves that this argument is invalid.
Lets name this argument form, again by what it does. Its Affirming the
Consequent. And any token argument that has this form will be invalid, so you
can now use this argument form as a template.
Some cases of Affirming the Consequent are quite obvious, and youd never be
fooled by them:
If an animal is a dog, then its a mammal. Bobs pet is a
mammal (it just gave live birth). Therefore Bobs pet is a dog.
Bob could very well have, for a example, a cat for a pet. A cat, then, is a
counterexample that illustrates how these premises fail to guarantee the truth of
this conclusion.
But sometimes, things are not so obvious:
The sign said Gold permit parking only. And I have a Gold
permit. So I should not have been ticketed for parking in the lot.
But there may be other necessary conditions, besides having a Gold permit, that
must be met, e.g., that the parking not be overnight. The sign merely states that
if one may park then one must have a Gold permit. And thats why this person
who was ticketed for overnight parking, has only a fallacious leg to stand on.
Lets name yet another argument and test it for validity:
pq
~p
~q
247
Rather than affirming the antecedent, this one is Denying the Antecedent. Here
is the truth table we need to test itnote the added columns for molecular
propositions ~p and ~q.
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
P2
~p
F
F
T
T
C
~q
F
T
F
T
P1
pq
T
F
T
T
Are there any circumstances [rows] in which the premises are true and the
conclusion is false? Yesthe third row. So Denying the Antecedent is an
invalid argument form wherever you might find it. Heres an example:
Whenever Kevin gets bogged down in mindless paper work for
the University, hes bummed out. But lately, he hasnt been
plagued with paper work. So he must not be bummed.
I get depressed for a gazillion reasons, mindless paper work being only one of
them. [Another being that a certain word-processing application is unable to
reliably deal with a fair number of tables in a modest-length document. Sorry,
but I needed to vent a bit.]
Lets do another one:
pq
~q
~p
The name should spring to mind: Denying the Consequent. Historically, this
goes by the name of Modus Tollens. It too is a very frequently used argument,
so its crucial to be able to quickly spot it in daily discourse and know whether
its valid or not. Look at its truth table and ask the magic question of validity:
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
C
~p
F
F
T
T
P2
~q
F
T
F
T
P1
pq
T
F
T
T
248
for inferring what follows when one is out of step with rules and regulations, for
instance:
In order to qualify for the stock options program, one must have
been employed full-time for at least one year. While you have
been here for one year, it was not as a full-time employee; so I
regret to inform you that you are not eligible to participate in the
Company stock options program.
Argument forms such as Denying the Consequent [and others!] can be hidden
from view sometimes. Here is an example:
If Peter showed up at the party, Paul did not have a good time.
But in fact Paul had a great time; so Peter did not go to the
party.
We would symbolize this argument as follows:
p ~g
g
~p
This is indeed an instance of Denying the Consequentthe second premise is
equivalent to saying that it is not the case that Paul did not have a good time,
thereby denying the consequent:
p ~g
~~g
~p
Lets test some arguments that have some other connectives. How about this
one?
pvq
~p
q
Lets call this argument form Denying the Disjunct. Is it valid?
p
T
T
F
F
C
q
T
F
T
F
P2
~p
F
F
T
T
~q
F
T
F
T
249
P1
pvq
T
T
T
F
Its valid. The reason I included that unused column for ~q, is to let you see that
it wouldnt matter which disjunct is denied, the other disjunct would validly
follow.
Heres an example of this argument form:
Ill be there for Thanksgiving or the Holidays. Oh, but now I see
by my calendar that Im already committed to be elsewhere for
Thanksgiving; so Ill be there for the Holidays.
BTW: I offer these examples to help you get a real feel for these argument
forms. If they dont work and you find better examples, please use them instead,
because theres nothing like a good example to help you learn these argument
forms and how to apply them.
How about this argument form?
pvq
p
~q
Call this Affirming the Disjunct. Is it valid?
P2
p
T
T
F
F
q
T
F
T
F
C
~q
F
T
F
T
~p
F
F
T
T
P1
pvq
T
T
T
F
We see, by the truth table, that Affirming the Disjunct is invalid. The first row
of the truth table tells us exactly the circumstances in which there is a
counterexample. [Mini-pop-quiz: Which row is the counterexample when the
other disjunct is affirmed?]
And heres an example:
Either Ill go to Minneapolis or Chicago to look at office
furniture. Since I looked at furniture in Minneapolis, I wont be
going to Chicago.
By looking at this example, you can see even more clearly why Affirming the
Disjunct is invalid. Its because its disjunction is an inclusive disjunction, which
can be true by having both its disjuncts true.
250
p
T
T
T
T
F
F
F
F
q
T
T
F
F
T
T
F
F
r
T
F
T
F
T
F
T
F
P1
pq
T
T
F
F
T
T
T
T
P2
qr
T
F
T
T
T
F
T
T
C
pr
T
F
T
F
T
T
T
T
Are there any rows in which the two premises are true while the conclusion is
false? No, so this is a valid argument form.
In fact, this is our old friend Barbara, just dressed in propositional clothing.
Your familiarity with this argument form in categorical form, should make it
easy for you to spot it in the field, so Ill spare you an example.
251
252
p
T
T
T
T
F
F
F
F
q
T
T
F
F
T
T
F
F
r
T
F
T
F
T
F
T
F
P1
pq
T
T
F
F
T
T
T
T
P2
qr
T
F
T
T
T
F
T
T
C
pr
T
F
T
F
T
T
T
T
But even though these two rows were interesting candidates for counterexamples,
they did not pan out, because they were not rows in which the premises were
both true. And thats why the argument is valid.
I propose we do some serious trimming on the truth table and adopt the short
truth table method for testing validity.
We cut right to the interesting rows of the truth table by assigning truth
values to the conclusion so as to make it false, and then see if, under those
truth values, we can make the premises all true.
Here, then, are the steps in applying the short truth table method for testing the
validity of prop arguments:
Step one: To apply the short truth table method, you must lay out your
argument horizontally, instead of vertically. [Stacking the argument vertically
does help to reveal its argument form, though.] A slash is used to indicate where
the premises end and the conclusion begins [some people indicate this with a
little pyramid of dots [] and others use both [/]. Ill just use the slash:
pq qr / pr
Step two: Assign the truth values necessary to make the conclusion false. To
indicate that we are making p r false, we put an F under the horseshoe. To
make p r false, we have to make p true and r false; so, we put a T under the p
and an F under the r.
pq qr / pr
TFF
Step three: Carry over your truth-value assignments. The truth values for p
and for r have now been determined for the rest of the test, so make those same
253
truth-values assignments to p and r wherever you find them in the premises. [Not
making the same assignments would be just plain inconsistent.]
pq qr / pr
T
F TFF
Step four: Assign the truth values necessary to make the premises true. Or at
least try to. Lets begin with the first premisein order to make p q true,
given that p is already true, we must make q true. So lets make those truth-value
assignments below.
pq qr / pr
TTT
F TFF
But when we carry that truth-valued assignment over to the second premise and
make q true in q r, we see that that would make q r false, in light of the fact
that r is already false:
pq qr / pr
TTT TFF TFF
Step five: The final verdict. If the premises c a n all be true while the
conclusion is false, we have thereby proved the argument invalid and have
provided a counterexample. Or, if the premises cannot all be true while the
conclusion is false, we have thereby proved the argument valid [as we just did
above].
Lets apply the short truth table method to the following argument:
pq
rs
pvr
qvs
The first order of business is to lay it out horizontally:
pq rs pvr / qvs
And now we do a kind of contra-Picard on the conclusion. Rather than Make
it so! we Make it not so! What does it take to make the conclusion, which is a
disjunction, false? Thats right, make both of its disjuncts false.
Important note: To apply the short truth table method, you must know
the truth-functional definitions of the connectivesknowing under what
254
conditions our basic molecular propositions are true and when they are
false should be effortless by now.
OK, heres where we are so far:
pq rs pvr / qvs
F
F
FFF
Now our project turns to that of making the premises all true, under these truthvalue assignments. Where should we begin?
Strategy suggestion: Begin where there has already been some work
done for youmake it easier on yourself. [Notice how much work it
would be to begin with the third premisep v r. There are three ways to
make that proposition true. So beginning there would almost be like
doing a regular truth table on the argument. Yuck!]
Lets begin with our first premise and then do the second premise. To get p q
true, p must be false. And to get r s true, r must be false. Lets enter those
truth-value assignments on our short truth table:
pq rs pvr / qvs
FTF FTF
FFF
But now, when we bring our truth values over to p v r, we see that it must be
false, since we made p false and r false.
pq rs pvr / qvs
FTF FTF FFF FFF
If we tried to make p v r true, for example, by making p true, look what happens:
pq rs pvr / qvs
TFF FTF TTF FFF
We see that we simply cant make all the premises true while the conclusion is
falsethe falsity of at least one premise is like a wrinkle in the carpetwhen we
stomp it out in the third premise, it just popped up in the first. Thats your proof
that the argument is valid!
The argument we just proved valid is a very popular one; its called the
Constructive Dilemma.
255
pq
rs
pvr
qvs
Be on the lookout for this important argument form. Sometimes the horns of
the dilemma are stated first, viz., the argument leads off with the disjunction.
Either I go to school full-time or I work full-time. But if I work
full time, Ill never get a better job. And if I go to school fulltime, Ill run up a lot of loans. So it looks as if Im screwed with
either a dead-end job or a bundle of debts.
Sometimes the horns of the dilemma can get extended by Hypothetical
Syllogisms. This is something newargument forms can join together to
build even more complex arguments. Heres an example:
pvr
pq
qt
rs
su
tvu
Arguments like this happens all the timeat least every Friday night for some of
us:
We can either make dinner or go out. If we go out, well just be
disappointed with the food, and that will spoil our evening. If
we make dinner, itll be better than restaurant swill, but well be
too pooped to enjoy it, and that will spoil our evening. So we are
doomed to have a lousy evening!
Heres yet another argument form for your listthis will be the last one, I
promise:
pq
rs
~q v ~s
~p v ~r
Let me illustrate its test for validity by means of the short truth tablesee if you
can describe the play-by-play of how I made my truth-value assignments:
256
pq rs ~qv~s / ~pv~r
TTT TTT FTFFT
FTFFT
This is called the Destructive Dilemma, and its a very popular valid argument
form.
If I take a winter vacation, I will have to skip preparing for
Spring Semester. But, if I take a summer vacation, Ill have to
skip prepping for Fall Semester. But Im going to have to prep
for at least one semester, so Im going to stay home either during
winter break or the summer.
Heres a little tip on how to remember the structures of these two dilemmas:
pq
rs
pvr
qvs
pq
rs
~q v ~s
~p v ~r
Constructive Dilemma
The disjunction of 2 cases of Affirming
the Antecedent
Destructive Dilemma
The disjunction of 2 cases of Denying
the Consequent
Often both horns of a dilemma can lead you to the same consequent, so that
youre damned if you do and damned if you dont. Heres an example:
If I dont drive into town tonight and return the video, Im out
three bucks. And if I dont stay home and send in my threedollars-off rebate coupon before it expires, Ill be out 3 bucks.
So.
257
Valid
pq
q
p
Invalid
pq
~p
~q
Invalid
pq
~q
~p
Valid
pvq
p
~q
Invalid
pvq
~p
q
Valid
pq
qr
pr
Hypothetical Syllogism
Valid
p v r
pq
rs
q v s
Constructive Dilemma
Valid
pq
r s
~q v ~s
~p v ~r
Destructive Dilemma
Valid
Here are all the argument forms weve introduced. You may want to make a
copy of this list, to help you get a good feel for the shapes of these arguments.
258
There are other argument forms, of course, but theyre either too trivial [e.g.,
Simplification: p q / p] or too rare [so just do a short truth table for them].
259
sms r
~r
~sms
This is an instance of Denying the Consequent, which is valid too.
There are only two ferries per day to the island. And, since he
didnt arrive on the second, he must have taken the first.
fvs
~s
f
This is a case of Denying the Disjunct, which is also valid.
To pass this course, one needs to practice diligently. To keep my
job at the hotel, I need to increase my afternoon hours. But I
dont have time to both practice sufficiently and work enough
afternoon hours at the hotel. So somethings got to give!
pc pd
kj >h
~pd v ~>h
~pc v ~kj
This is a Destructive Dilemmavalid.
The rule doesnt hold true for us, because we made too much
money that year. It says, If your income was under $20,000 for
the year 2000, then if you incurred any moving expenses, they
are completely deductible.
<$20K (me d)
~<$20K
~(me d)
This is Denying the Antecedent. Its invalid.
There was a little something new in this last one: Molecular propositions can just
as well be used as the building blocks of argument forms.
Since a receipt is required for the rebate, he must have received
the rebate, because I was the checkout teller that night and I
remember handing him his receipt.
260
reb rec
rec
reb
This is Affirming the Consequent, which is invalid.
I know he didnt major in Philosophy, in view of the fact that
people in the Society & Law Program major in either Philosophy
or History, and I know he chose History.
pvh
h
~p
This is Affirming the Disjunctinvalid.
If someone wins arguments only by using informal fallacies, that
is intellectually dishonest. And that is sufficient reason to not
trust what such a person claims. Rush Limbaughs stock in trade
is winning arguments with informal fallacies. And thats why
his claims cant be trusted.
wif id
id ~t
wif
~t
Here we use two argument forms to get to the conclusion: Hypothetical
Syllogism and Affirming the Antecedent. First we use a Hypothetical Syllogism
to distill the first and the second premises to the subconclusion, wif ~t. And
then we add the remaining premise to draw the conclusion by means of
Affirming the Antecedent. Since both of these argument forms are valid, our
overall march to the conclusion is valid. If, however, any step we use en route
to the conclusion is invalid, the entire argument is invalid too.
Production at this plant will continue, but only if costs can be
cut. And that will be accomplished only with the cooperation of
the union. But the union has just promised to strike rather than
cooperate with the wage freeze. The plant closing is inevitable.
p cc
cc u
~u
~p
261
There are two ways of analyzing this argument by means of argument forms. We
could combine the first and the second premises and infer that p u, by means
of Hypothetical Syllogism. And then we would combine that with the remaining
premise, to infer our conclusion, by means of Denying the Consequent.
p cc
cc u
[p u]
~u
~p
HS
DC
Or, we could combine the third and the second premises and infer that ~cc, by
means of Denying the Consequent. And then combine that with the first premise,
to infer our conclusion, again by means of Denying the Consequent.
cc u
~u
[~cc]
p cc
~p
DC
DC
Both analyses prove that this argument is valid, since both of these sets of
argument forms are valid. But which analysis is most likely to be how the author
thinks that their premises act as reasons to believe the conclusion? In all likelihood, it is our first analysis that best captures how someone would infer the
conclusion on the basis of these premises. It would be easier to progress towards
the conclusion rather than work sort of backwards to it.
This is an extra aspect of analyzing an argument by means of argument
forms: You are not only trying to assess the arguments validity, but also
trying to capture as best you can the authors inference processtheir
mental steps to their conclusion.
Heres a worst case scenario for you:
He must be hiding in the basement. Hes either in the attic or the
bottom floors. But we checked the attic already and didnt find
him, so that leaves the bottom floors. If so, hed pick a level
where you couldnt see him through the windows. And that
would be the basement.
Here we have an argument consisting of three argument forms, all of which are
valid; so, the overall argument is valid. Heres how it goes:
262
a v bf
~a
bf
bf ~s
~s b
[bf b]
b
Hypothetical Syllogism
Affirming the Antecedent
OK, after that one, you should be able to handle pretty much anything life will
throw you by way of argument forms.
263
Next, we turn to the project of trying to make all the premises true, which would
prove the argument invalid. To find any such counterexample, we must investigate all three ways of making the conclusion false, if thats what it takes. All we
need to find in order to prove the argument invalid is one such counterexample.
Lets investigate the first way first:
~r~p ~rc ~ps /cs
FTFFT FTTF FTTF FFF
We couldnt make the first premise true, under this way of making the conclusion
false. Lets try the second way of making the conclusion false:
~r~p ~rc ~ps /cs
FTF
FTTF
T FFT
Again, we couldnt make the first premise truewe didnt even have to give ~p a
truth-value assignment to know this.
Lets investigate the third way of making the conclusion false:
~r~p ~rc ~ps /cs
FFT
T FTTF TFF
Once again we cant make the first premise true, and we didnt even have to give
~r a truth-value assignment to know this. We have now done an exhaustive
search and can find no way to make the premises all true while the conclusion is
falseand that, after all, is the claim of validity. So this proves that the
argument is valid.
Always remember, as you test arguments for validity using the short truth
table method: Your failure to make the premises all true is the arguments
success at validity; your success is the arguments failure.
Pop quiz:
1. In the middle of the last problem, we were investigating if we
could make the premises true when the conclusion was false in
this way:
~r~p ~rc ~ps /cs
F
T FFT
264
265
When George goes Sherry goes too. But Sherry will go if and only if
Larry doesnt. And if Rose wont go, Larry will. To make matters
worse, either George is going or Rose isnt. So George is going, but just
in case Larry isnt.
GS S~L ~RL Gv~R / G~L
FFTF
TFFT
There are two ways of making the conclusion false; lets check the first way first:
GS S~L ~RL Gv~R / G~L
FTT TTTF FTTF FFFT FFTF
Three out of four isnt good enough. Lets try the second possible way of
making the conclusion false:
GS S~L ~RL Gv~R / G~L
TFF FTFT
T T
TFFT
And we see right away that we cant make the first two premises true, so we have
demonstrated that this is a valid argument.
Heres a last one, the likes of which you might find as you are trying to think
through the terms of a service agreement:
If the seal has not been broken and routine servicing has been performed,
the warranty is still in effect. The owner is responsible, however, for the
damage only if routine service was not performed or the seal was broken.
Therefore, even if routine service was not performed, the warranty is in
effect.
( ~ B R ) W D ( ~ R v B) / ~ R W
TFFF T F
TF
TFFF
FTFF T F
TF
TFFF
Notice how there are two ways of making the first premise true, given the single
way to make the conclusion false.
Now lets bring those possible truth values for B over to the second premise and
see what happens:
266
(~BR)W
TFFF T F
TFFF T F
FTFF T F
FTFF T F
D ( ~ R v B) / ~ R W
T T TFTF
TFFF
F T TFTF
TFFF
T T TFTT
TFFF
F T TFTT
TFFF
We find that under each of the two ways of making the first premise true, there
are two ways of making the second premise true. This makes for a grand total of
four counterexamples, thus demonstrating the invalidity of this argument. We
only had to find one of these, to prove our case against this argument. But by
finding all four, we have done a real service to the person using the argument,
thereby showing them the extent of circumstances in which these premises fail to
guarantee the truth of the conclusion. This is particularly important when youre
the user of the argument, wondering under which circumstances they can rely on
the warranty referred to in the conclusion and when they cant!
Pop quiz: See how many counterexamples can you find when
we change the conclusion to: Therefore, the warranty is in
effect, unless the owner is responsible for the damage.
( ~ B R ) W D ( ~ R v B) / ~ D W
267
268
Index
INDEX
Categorical Statements 153-66
Categories 153
Cogency
conditions of See ARG
conditions
definition of 36
Coherence Theory 91-2
Conceptual Analysis 55-9
Conclusion
definition of 6
implicit 27-8
indicators 9-10
Conditional 227-9
antecedent of 227
consequent of 227
necessary conditions of 228
sufficient conditions of 228
Conditional Argument 108
Conjunction 226
Conjuncts 226
Constructive Dilemma 254-7
Contradictories 171
Contrapositive 182-8
Contraries 189-92
Converse 174-80
Critical Thinking
definition of 3
elements of 3-4
goal of 2
study of 1-267 ;-)
Criticism, types of 48-50
A
Ad Hominem 131-37
Acceptability 32-3, 88-117
coherence theory of 91-2
foundationalist theory of 89-91
relativity of, 92-3
Accepting Premises 108-17
Affirming the Antecedent 246-7
Affirming the Consequent 247
Affirming the Disjunct 250
Ambiguity 70-7
Analogy 120-6
Appeal to Authority 94-8
Appeal to False Authority 96-8
Appeal to Force 148-9
Appeal to Ignorance 141-6
Appeal to Popularity 146-8
Appeal to Past Practices 148
Appeal to Precedent 148
Appeal to Tradition 147-8
ARG Conditions 37-8
See acceptability, relevance, and
groundedness
Argument
anatomy of 26-31
definition of 6
diagrams 29-30
explanation, differs from 19-22
identification of 6-25
subargument 26-7
test for 22-3
Argument Forms 245-63
Assertion 10-11
D
Deductive Argument 152-267
definition of 39
inductive argument, differs from
39-44
relevance condition 119-20
Definition
circular 60
counterexamples of 55
definition of 53
B
Bar, the 163
Barbara 213
Begging the Question 106-7
Biconditional 229, 237
C
Categorical Logic 152-221
269
Index
definiendum of 60
definiens of 60
necessary conditions of 55
persuasive 67-8
question begging 60
stipulative 64-7
sufficient conditions of 55
too broad 56
too narrow 56
virtues of 59-60
Denying the Antecedent 248
Denying the Consequent 248-9
Denying the Disjunct 249-50
Description 16
Destructive Dilemma 256-7
Dictionary Definitions 59-60, 63-4
Disjunction 227
exclusive and inclusive 240-1
Disjuncts 227
Dot, the 226
Double Negation 188
E
Enthymeme 214-21
Equivocation 72-5
Equivalent Categorical Statements
173-89
Equivalence 229-30
Euphemistic Language 69-70
Explanation
argument, differs from 19-22
types of 17-9
Existential Commitment 159-61,
204-7
External Negation 192
J
Jabberwocky 51
L
Loaded Language 68-9
Logical Connectives 224-31
Logical Entailment 34-5
mere intimation, differs from
104-5
Logical Impossibility 34-5
F
False Analogy 123-4
False Dichotomy 190
Foundationalism 89-91
G
Genetic Fallacy 133
Giere, Ronald 173, 268
Govier, Trudy 38, 44
M
Main Connective, the 242-4
Mere Intimation 104-5
270
Index
N
Non sequitur 118
O
Objective 12-3
Obverse 180-2
P
Persuasive Definition 67-8
Poisoning the Well 133
Predicate 154
Premise
definition of 6
false 99
false assumption, involving
102-3
implicit 27-8
inconsistent 99-102
indicators 9
Preston, Ivan 104
Propositional Logic 222-67
Propositional Arguments 244-68
Proposition
atomic 224
definition of 224
molecular 224
R
Redefinist Fallacy 64
Red Herring 119
Reductio ad Absurdum 108-17
Relativism 12-5
Relevance 37-8, 118-51
Reverse the Argument 106
U
Use-Mention Distinction 61-2
V
Vagueness 75-87
Validity
definition of 35-6, 42-7
See Venn Diagram, Truth Table,
and Short Truth Table
Venn Diagram 166-221
S
Short Truth Table 252-7, 263-7
Slippery Slope Fallacy 79-87
Soundness 36-7
Square of Opposition 171
Standard Categorical Form 155-65
W
Wedge, the 227
Well-formed formula 242
271
C r i t i c a l Th i n k i n g & C T So f t w a r e
A completely computer-assisted, step-by-step guide to developing
your critical-thinking and logical-reasoning skills.
Whats covered in Critical Thinking?
Argument identification
Anatomy of an argument
Conditions for good arguments
Use and abuse of definitions
Use and abuse of language
Rhetorical tricks
Categorical arguments
Propositional arguments