Broad Definition: Have Objectives and Tend To Choose The Correct Way of Achieving Them. "Rationality."
Broad Definition: Have Objectives and Tend To Choose The Correct Way of Achieving Them. "Rationality."
Broad Definition: Have Objectives and Tend To Choose The Correct Way of Achieving Them. "Rationality."
School of Law
D. Friedman
This outline contains what I said, what I think I said, and what I ought to have said, so discrepancies
between what it contains and what you remember are not necessarily due to your poor memory.
I. Mechanics of Course:
A. Written material will consist of:
1. Posner: A big book, by a leading figure in the field, covering much more material than
we will have time for.
2. Lots of articles which will be handed out in class; note that in some cases only part of
the article is assigned.
3. An outline of the lecture, which will be handed out each week for the preceding week,
deus volenti. You're reading it.
B. There will be two midterms.
D. The final will cover everything, and be mostly or entirely essay.
E. Previous year's lecture notes and exams are or will be available on the web page
and in the library.
II. Sketch of course:
A. This week-introduction
B. Part I: Economic Analysis of Law, organized by ideas.
C. Part II: Organized by legal field.
III. What is economics?
A. An approach to understanding behavior, based on the assumption that Individuals
have objectives and tend to choose the correct way of achieving them. "Rationality."
B. Some Examples:
1. Why have locks on doors?
a. A sufficiently determined burglar can get into anything short of a bank vault,
with a sledgehammer and crowbar or through the window.
b. A lock makes it harder, thus more work and a greater chance of being caught,
thus a less profitable project.
c. So we put locks on our doors because we believe that burglars are rational.
2. A policeman has evidence that will convict a criminal; what does he do with it?
a. Convictions costs the criminal $50,000, benefits the policeman's career by
$10,000
b. Dragnet answer: arrest the criminal.
c. Economics answer: Sell the evidence to the criminal for some price between
$10,000 and $50,000
d. To keep this from happening, some of the policemen have to be watching the
other policemen instead of the criminals.
e. The solution proposed by Becker and Stigler was a bounty system, where the
policeman receives as salary the fine paid by the convicted criminal. If he takes a
bribe, he is merely cutting out the middleman.
f. Which is how our civil system works-we call the "bribe" an out of court
settlement.
3. Civil forfeiture
a. Under Federal law and the law of many states, property used in certain crimes
can be seized by the government, without proving that the owner was guilty of
anything.
b. In at least some states, the value of the seized property goes to the police
department that seized it.
c. Which gives police departments an incentive to look for rich people they can
find (or create) evidence against, rather than criminals in general.
d. A similar problem exists with punitive damages.
4. If we impose the maximum possible penalty for armed robbery, the additional penalty
for murder if you are already committing armed robbery is zero, so we have made it in
the interest of armed robbers to kill their victims.
IV. What is the Economic Analysis of Law?
A. First Project: The consequences of legal rules.
1. If we impose the maximum possible penalty for armed robbery, ...
a. The implication is not necessarily that we shouldn't do it-it will deter some
armed robberies
b. But increase the number of armed robberies with murder
c. And we should take that into account in deciding whether to execute armed
robbers.
2. Plea bargaining:
a. It seems as though it should weaken punishments, since a defendant will only
accept a plea bargain if he thinks it is a better deal than the risk of being tried and
convicted.
b. But it may strengthen them. Prosecutors have limited resources; if 90% of
defendants plea bargain, resources can be concentrated on the remaining 10%,
making conviction more likely-and making defendants willing to accept harsher
bargains.
3. Requiring CD players in cars. Seems to benefit consumers-until we take account of
the effect on the price of cars. The same argument applies to requiring hot water in
apartments, safe jobs, ... . Fixing one term of a contract in favor of one party is not in
general a transfer, since prices, or other terms in the contract, shift to compensate.
4. Requiring seat belts. Accidents are the result of rational decisions-how fast to drive
etc. Making cars safer makes risky driving cheaper, which increases the amount of it.
Sam Peltzman actually observed this result by statistical analysis of accident rates before
and after a sharp increase in required safety equipment.
B. Second Project: Predicting legal rules.
1. The Posner Conjecture: Common Law tends to be economically efficient.
2. One basis for this conjecture might be a plausible mechanism by which efficient law
would be generated. In my opinion, Posner has never provided one.
3. An alternative basis might be evidence that the observed rules of the common law
tend to be the same rules that economic theory tells us are efficient. Posner offers a lot of
such evidence. One problem is that the conclusions of economic theory are not always
clear cut, so a clever economist who knows what the rule is might be able to construct
arguments for why it is efficient-and might be able to do so for whichever alternative the
law chose.
4. An alternative approach to predicting legal rules-legislated ones-is public choice
theory, which tries to apply economics to the political marketplace. We will probably not
be covering that in this course.
5. This project is also a positive one-explaining what the law is, not what it should be.
C. Third Project: Evaluating Legal Rules-Efficiency as a norm.
1. Controversial, but ...
2. Economic efficiency is a value, and maybe the one law can best achieve
3. Allocation vs distribution
V. What is economic analysis of law good for? Why should people study it?
A. One attraction of the economic analysis of law, from the standpoint of legal
scholars (or potential legal scholars) is that it ties together diverse areas of law,
providing a common theoretical structure.
B. It is also useful for understanding economics, because you learn about ideas by
trying to concretize them.
1. "Property" sounds like a simple idea-and isn't.
a. Does ownership of land include the air above-to what height? The earth
underneath? Oil in the earth underneath?
b. What can you do to protect your ownership? Physically keep people out (build a
high wall)? Shoot trespassers? Sue trespassers-but only for damage actually done?
2. "Cause an externality" seems like a simple concept-and isn't. When I play loud music
while my roommate wants to sleep, there is a resulting cost-but it would be eliminated
either by my turning off my music or by my roommate deciding to get up and party.
3. Coase revolutionized our understanding of externalities, market failure, etc., in part by
looking at how the common law of nuisance treated such problems.
4. "Cause" is also a difficult concept more generally. Consider the case of two hunters
simultaneously shooting a third-one in the head, one in the heart. Who caused the third
hunter's death? Neither-and both.
C. The law is also useful to economists as a vast pool of interesting puzzles.
D. And as data.
1. How people do things is a fact-evidence.
2. When you prove they would be better off doing things differently, you have probably
demonstrated a flaw in your theory-since people generally know what actions are in their
interest.
VI. I have been offering a broad definition of economics, one that goes far beyond
prices, unemployment, and the like. What is the relation between economics defined in
that way and economics more narrowly defined-what you find in the typical micro text?
A. The latter has been worked out in more detail.
B. and it helps us understand economics in the broader sense.
1. To understand marriage, use ideas developed in explaining long term contracts
between firms. Talking about a marriage market is not merely a metaphor-it is a real
market, even if the prices are not explicit or in money.
2. To understand your three year old's apparently irrational behavior ("I want ice cream
and will throw a tantrum if I don't get it, even though you will then send me up to my
room without any ice cream") think about the logic of commitment strategies in ordinary
economics. If he persuades you that he has committed himself strongly enough, next
time you may give him the ice cream to avoid the tantrum.
C. The broad approach helps us intuit the narrow. We do a lot of rational choosing in
our daily lives, and can apply the intuitions developed there to understanding the
behavior of firms, workers, etc.
VII. What is economic efficiency? (Posner calls it "Wealth Maximization")
A. The problem-evaluating different systems of rules, their outcomes, etc.
1. By whose values?
2. How aggregated?
B. The economic solution.
1. Revealed preference: Heroin or Insulin, the fact that someone is willing to pay lots of
money to get it is evidence that it is valuable to him. How valuable? It is worth to him
the maximum amount he would be willing, if necessary, to pay for it.
2. Aggregate effects across people by using willingness to pay as a common unit. We are
using value (utility measured by dollar willingness to pay) rather than utility (units of
pleasure, or happiness, or something similar). A dollar might represent more utility to
one person (poor-or materialistic) than to another (rich-or ascetic) but it represents, by
definition, the same value. So we count a change that benefits Bill Gates by $10 and
hurts a homeless person by $9 as an improvement, which seems wrong.
3. Note that value measured in dollars is not the same thing as pieces of green paper. If I
am willing to pay $400 for a new printer and buy it for $300, I end up with $300 less
money-but I am $100 better off than before the deal.
C. Defense of the economic solution.
1. If we wish to describe behavior, it is revealed preference, not "value as known in the
mind of God," that is the relevant tool.
2. If we wish to predict outcomes, willingness to pay is more relevant than utility.
Whether lobbying, litigating, or simply buying goods on the marketplace, one man's
dollar will have about the same effect as another's, independent of how much happiness
a dollar represents to each.
3. What about using efficiency as a normative criterion-to decide how society should be
organized?
a. Both elements are then problems, but ...
b. It is not clear one can do better. God is not available to run the society. Other
people are available to make choices for us, but even if they (sometimes) know
what is good for me better than I do, they are less certain to seek my good than I
am. They may take the opportunity to seek their own good at my expense.
c. Many economic choices involve gains and losses to large and diverse groups, in
which case differences in utility/dollar may average out.
d. Even if efficiency is a good proxy for utility, however, is utility all that matters?
If there are utility monsters (people who feel much more intently than the rest of
us do) should we devote all of our resources to their pleasure? If you can save the
lives of three people about to be lynched by framing one innocent person for the
crime, should you do it?
e. Utility is probably not all that matters, but it is one big thing that matters, and if
we know how to maximize it and don't know how to maximize the rest of what
matters (or cannot agree about what it does), then rules that maximize utility (or
efficiency as a proxy for utility) may be the best we can do.
D. Efficient vs Inefficient outcome: "Efficient" is a sort of outer bound benchmark,
the best result we could hope to achieve by any economic system.
1. I define a "bureaucrat god" as someone who knows everything anyone in the society
knows, and has unlimited ability to calculate how to coordinate people's actions and to
make them do what he tells them to.
2. An outcome is efficient if a bureaucrat god could not improve it ("improve" in the
sense we have been discussing-make a change that produces total benefits larger than
total costs).
3. If an outcome is efficient, no change in the economic/legal system can improve it,
since we have no tools available that the bureaucrat god does not also have.
4. If an outcome is inefficient, we might be able to improve it. But we also might not,
since we have no bureaucrat gods available to run our economy.
E. Other definitions of efficiency. [I didn't get to this part in class]
1. Pareto:
a. An improvement is a change that benefits someone, hurts nobody. This
definition avoids interpersonal comparison, but ...
b. In practice, few changes in legal rules and the like are pareto improvements.
2. Hicks/Kaldor:
a. An improvement is a change that would be a pareto improvement if combined
with suitable transfers among those affected.
b. This almost always gives the same conclusion as Marshall's definition (what I
started out explaining).
c. Because if there are net benefits, then the gainers gain enough to compensate the
losers, and if the gainers gain enough to compensate the losers, then there are net
benefits.
d. Actually, there is an exception to this apparently obvious conclusion, explained
in my article "Does Altruism Produce Efficient Outcomes? Marshall vs Kaldor" on
my academic web page.
3. Both the Kaldor and Pareto approach make it look as though you are not trading off
gains to one person against losses to another, when in fact you are. That is why I prefer
Marshall's approach.
E. What matters is that you understand these ideas, not that you agree with them.
1. Accept rationality as a working hypothesis for this course.
2. Take Posner conjecture as a conjecture, look at evidence for and against.
3. Feel however you like on the third project.
1/21/97
1/28/97: Insurance
VII. Application to product liability. Who is liable for damage done by exploding Coke
bottles?
A. Consider two alternative legal rules:
1. Caveat Emptor (latin for "let the buyer beware"): You take your good as it is, defects
and all. If the coke bottle explodes, the injured consumer pays his own bills.
2. Caveat Venditor ("let the seller beware"): If something goes wrong with the product,
the seller is liable for the damage.
3. I am treating the distinction as sharper than it really is. If your wife shoots you with
your gun, something has gone wrong, but the fact that a gun shoots the person it is
pointed at does not generally count as a product defect, even if it happens to have been
pointed at the wrong person. So implicitly we are talking only about some subset of
"things going wrong" that are plausibly associated with something wrong with the
product.
4. But that can still be a large and hazy category.
B. Insurance, risk spreading argument: The Coke company can self-insure, the
customer cannot.
1. If Coca-cola is selling ten billion bottles a year, of which one in a million will blow
up, they can count on almost exactly 10,000 exploding coke bottles per year. It is still a
cost, but not much of a risk, since the size of the cost can be predicted with accuracy.
2. So transferring the cost to Coca-cola reduces the risk aversion part of the cost. Before
the change, the customer faced a very uncertain cost. After the change, neither party
faces a very uncertain cost.
3. This only works if the events in question are independent. One bottle blowing up does
not affect the probability that another one will.
4. On the other hand, Coke cannot self-insure against the risk that legal rules will shift
against them. If courts decide to award much larger damages to consumer injured by
exploding Coke bottles, that will apply to all of the bottles, so the effect does not average
out.
C. Moral hazard argument:
1. If the relevant margin for control is care in manufacturing, then liability (caveat
venditor) reduces the moral hazard problem.
2. If the relevant margin is careful use by the buyer, then caveat venditor increases the
problem.
D. Adverse selection argument:
1. What do we assume about consumer information?
2. If consumers cannot observe quality or judge by reputation, then we have a lemons
problem with caveat emptor--everybody produces a below optimal quality, because a
higher quality, being unobservable, cannot command a higher price.
3. A different way of saying this is to consider a situation where the seller knows how
safe the coke bottle is, the buyer does not.
a. If he sells me a coke bottle, I don't know what I am buying (since I don't know
the risk of explosion and do care), so don't know whether it is worth the price
b. I buy too much if it is riskier than I think (since I am underestimating the true
price--or, if you prefer, overestimating the true value), too little if it is safer than I
think.
c. If he sells me acoke bottle with a guarantee, he knows what he is selling, since
he knows the chance that he will have to pay off on the guarantee.
d. And I know the value to me of what I am buying. I don't know the chance of an
explosion--but I don't care, since he has insured me against that risk.
4. If consumers are well informed about average quality by firm, then caveat emptor is
fine from both an adverse selection and a moral hazard standpoint. No moral hazard,
because Coke has an incentive to provide good quality control so that consumers will
want to buy their product.
5. Adverse selection can also apply on the customer's side. Under caveat venditor, I don't
want to sell a car to someone who will use it for drag racing, then sue me when there is
an accident.
E. So far it looks as though we can simply balance risk aversion, moral hazard, and
adverse selection to choose the optimal rule.
1. Either the optimal broad rule-- "producers are always liable," "producers are never
liable"
2. Or have the court look at the product and decide which rule is preferable.
3. Or have the court look at the particular facts, and decide which rule is preferable
under those circumstances. Coke is liable unless you were shaking the bottle. This is the
approach embodied in negligence rules.
4. As we go from more general to more specific, the amount of detailed knowledge the
court needs increases, and the predictability of the result decreases.
F. The conclusion seems to be:
1. that if consumers are well informed about average product quality by firm, or can
judge individual products, the optimal rule is caveat emptor.
2. Ditto if the main risks comes from decisions by consumers (shaking a warm coke
bottle up and down while making a point in an argument--you can't idiot proof
everything, because idiots are too damn ingenioius).
3. Caveat venditor is the optimal rule if consumer is poorly informed both about
individual product and firm average, and the important decisions relative to accidents are
decisions by the firm.
4. And the advantage tilts towards caveat venditor if the loss is large and the producer is
much better able to self insure than the consumer. Note that not all imaginable cases
involve a small buyer and a big seller--consider GM as a buyer of labor.
5. But ...
F. Litigation cost and insurance:
1. So far, we have not been talking about insurance in the literal sense--we have a coke
company, a customer, but no insurance companies.
2. Why not? Instead of asking whether people want protection against risk, why not ask
whether tort liability is the cheapest way to produce it? What about ordinary insurance?
3. It has two big advantages, one disadvantage.
a. An insurance company wants a reputation for paying out readily; a firm may
well want the opposite reputation. A reputation for being tough might make
consumers less willing to buy the product--but in order to justify caveat venditor,
we must assume that consumers are poorly informed. A reputation for being tough
makes injured consumers (and their attornies) less willing to sue--and tort attornies
may be well informed about the litigation reputation of the firms they consider
suing.
b. Risk aversion doesn't depend on whose fault it was, so product liability is lousy
insurance. What if you get hurt and it wasn't due to a faulty product? You are
better off buying insurance that covers injuries from a wide range of causes.
c. Disadvantage--product liability may put the incentive somewhere useful (on the
firm that could take greater precautionsnot to make defective products), insurance
doesn't (except to the extent that your health insurer mails you medical tips, etc.)
4. One advantage of letting the loss lie where it falls is that nobody has to sue anybody,
so you don't have any litigation cost.
VIII. We have been running through arguments about how to decide whether or not
the law should force Coke to "insure" its customers against exploding Coke bottles.
Why doesn't the law make these calculations for ordinary insurance, deciding for
you whether you are insured or not?
A. Because under ordinary circumstances, you have the right incentive to make
them for yourself. You get risk protection, pay moral hazard plus administrative
costs.
B. Where that is not true, there is an argument for government insurance:
1. Mandatory auto insurance--to make sure that if you cause an accident, you can pay for
it.
2. National health insurance--if we believe that the rest of us won't let you die in the
street, so your decision not to get insured may impose costs on us.
3. Or if we think that the adverse selection problem, which gives an inefficient outcome
on the private market, is sufficiently serious.
4. This is a public approach analogous to a group policy, which is a private way of
controlling adverse selection.
II. Examples:
A. Scissors, Paper, Stone: a 2 player zero-sum game.
The Von Neuman solution: Each player rolls a die each time. 1-2 Scissors, 3-4
Paper, 5-6 stone. If I do that, then whatever you do I will, on average, win 1/3rd of
the time, lose 1/3rd, tie 1/3rd, for an expected payoff of 0. I cannot do better than
that because you can hold my payoff to zero by playing that strategy, and you
cannot do better because I can hold yours to zero by playing that strategy. So we
have a mixed strategy that is the VN solution
First Step
Second Step
At the bottom of the tree, player 2 on the second round knows that he is better off
confessing, so we can eliminate the "don't confess" option (grey on First Step
figure), and similarly for player 1. After eliminating those branches, we are left
with the Second Step figure, and each party, knowing what will happen at the
second play, can calculate he is better off confessing. An example of subgame
perfect equilibrium.
III. Ex Ante
Ante, ex Post
Post:
A. Consider two different approaches to preventing auto accidents:
1. Ex Ante--laws against speeding, required brake inspections, laws against DUI, etc.
2. Ex Post--tort liability, criminal penalties for drunk drivers in accidents, etc.
B. Consider the treatment of attempted murder:
1. If we are punishing ex post, according to damage actually done, attempted murder is
not a crime since nobody was killed. The bullet went into a nearby tree--which is doing
fine.
2. If we are punishing ex ante, according to the effects we predict behavior will have on
average, then attempted murder is a crime--shooting at people results, on average, in
killing some of them.
3. For a further puzzle, consider the (moral?) question of why we punish murder more
severely than attempted murder. If punishment reflects desert--what the crime tells us
about the wickedness of the perpetrator--shouldn't the punishment be the same? Being a
bad shot is not a moral virtue.
4. What about the case of impossible attempts--trying to kill someone by sticking pins in
a voodoo doll? Should that be a crime?
C. What are the advantages of ex post?
1. Ex post has some of the advantage of effluent fees over regulation. The court must
measure damage done, but doesn't have to know the relationship between precautions
and accidents--the driver provides that.
2. Nor does the court have to be able to monitor behavior in order to punish its
consequences, and thus deter it.
3. The driver has a lot of private information about costly activities that are hard to
monitor. Driving when sleepy, angry, paying attention to the conversation instead of the
road, ...
4. On the other hand, both methods use the driver's private information about how costly
the precaution is (in that respect, both are analogous to effluent fees), since with speed
limits, a driver can still violate them-and pay the ticket-if he thinks doing so is important.
5. Ex post has the further advantage that measuring the costs easier after they have
happened.
D. Advantages of ex ante?
1. Popular wrong answer: "ex post doesn't prevent accidents." Sure it does--by deterring
them.
2. Risk aversion--do you want to lose your house, all your property, and be indentured
for five years if you make a mistake driving?
3. Other punishment costs--can't collect ten million dollar fines.
4. What can we do that is equivalent in deterrent effect to one chance in a million of a
ten million dollar fine?
5. Maybe one chance in a million of execution, or life imprisonment, or ...
6. None of which pay us anything.
7. So ex post forces us to use punishments which are large, and as a result inefficient.
E. Implication:
1. People are risk averse only for large losses. So small ex post punishments are
unambiguously superior to ex ante.
2 So an entirely ex ante system, with no ex post costs, cannot be the right answer
3. We want ex post at least equal to the largest fine you can pay without serious risk
aversion costs.
4. Plus possibly some ex ante if that isn't large enough.
F. Freedom of contract solution?
1. Require insurance for appropriate amount.
2. Permit insurance company to impose ex ante rules as a condition of insuring you.
3. When the cops stop you for speeding, they check your insurance to see whether you
have agreed not to speed.
4. Higher tech version--they scan the barcode on your bumper to find out what traffic
laws they are enforcing on you on behalf of your insurance company.
5. This sounds odd, but the equivalent is common for fire insurance etc.--without help
from the cops. You agree to certain precautions as a condition of insurance.
G. Note that ex ante/ex post can work at several levels. My speeding might or might
not cause an accident, which might cause a variable level of damage.
1. Act---->(maybe accident)---->varying damage if accident
2. Pure ex ante is on act. Pure ex post depends only on damage.
3. Intermediate case: punishment is triggered by injury, but does not depend on damage
done.
4. To some extent this is implicit in drunk driving laws, for example, since you are much
more likely to be tested if you run into something. And the crime of murder does not
depend on the age of the victim, although we also have an element of pure ex ante in the
crime of attempted murder. Are there any pure cases of a punishment that depends on the
accident happening but not on the damage done?
V. Consider the difference among three alternative approaches to controlling behavior that does an
uncertain amount of damage:
A. Base punishment upon what the court believes the risks were.
B. Base punishment upon what the court believes the criminal thought the risks were.
A. A works if the court has superior knowledge and can define the rules determining
punishment in a way that makes it in the interest of the actor to act as the court wishes.
1. "It is illegal to drive more than 55 mph" as opposed to "it is illegal to drive in a way likely to
cause accidents."
2. The penalty can be adjusted so that it reflects the court's view of damage done.
3. One common special case is where the court doesn't think it can distinguish risks among
similar cases, so imposes a fixed punishment based on the average damage over all cases.
Loses on "superior knowledge" but gains on litigation cost, since it is a bright line rule.
B. B uses information that is inferior to the criminal's information (since it is information
about the criminal's information).
1. If punishment is proportional to damage done and criminals are risk neutral, C gives the
same result as B would if it were done perfectly, (see my Payne v Tennessee article for the
demonstration).
2. B might be superior either because it produces lower punishment cost (criminal can pay a
fine equal to the expected damage but not one equal to the maximum possible damage) or
because the optimal punishment is not the expected value of the punishments appropriate for
the offenses done with certainty. This gets into details of optimal punishment theory that are
discussed in the article, and will be covered later in the course.
3. B requires more work by the court than C, since under C the court simply observes what
happens and lets the criminal to the expected punishment calculation for himself when he is
deciding whether to commit the crime.
C. Under C, the criminal (or tortfeasor) uses his estimate of the probability of each of the
possible consequences of his act (killing a high value or low value victim, running his car
into a tree or a person), plus his knowledge of the punishment for each consequence, to
calculate the expected punishment.
D. B vs C is really ex ante vs ex post, without the court trying to take advantage of any
superior information it might have and the actor lack.
E. Examples:
A. You may not discharge a gun within city limits (but more severe punishment, in practice, if
you hit someone). Drug laws (if based on risk that user will commit crimes under the
influence). These also fit the pattern of combining some ex ante with some ex post.
B: Any law that sets a fixed punishment for a crime, independent of actual damage done.
a. Fairly common in criminal law, which uses broad categories, such as petty larceny and
grand larceny, rather than making punishment depend directly on damage done.
b. Payne v Tennessee was about whether the opposite policy was unconstitutional in the
capital punishment case.
C. The normal rule in tort law. This fits the pattern of tort law using money payments, which
are low cost punishments--but ... .
a. If tortfeasors are judgement proof against high judgements, it might be better to make
each tortfeasor liable for the average damage done by such torts rather than the damage
done by his tort.
b. One argument for the eggshell skull rule is that if no damage were done, no damages
would have been paid.
c. But one can imagine torts where it is easier to measure the average damage than the
actual damage. Suppose, for example, a reactor releases radiation which raises the cancer
rate by 10%. Noboby knows which cancer patients would not have gotten it save for the
leak.
VI. "Impossible attempts": Should there be a penalty for attempting to kill someone
by a method that cannot work?
A. Argument against--we don't mind if people stick pins in voodoo dolls, so why
impose costs on us and the attempted murderers to prevent it?
B. Argument for: The legal rule isn't about voodoo, it is about methods that don't
work. There must be some uncertainty about what methods work, or nobody would
use the ones that don't.
C. Consider a rational murderer choosing between voodoo and poison:
1. Rational believer in voodoo?
2. Why not--we all believe in, and under some circumstances trust our lives to, things we
don't really understand, and trust because people we trust tell us they work.
3. If he knows it doesn't work, he won't use it.
4. If he is certain it works, our legal rule (punishment for impossible attempts) has no
effect, since he is certain it does not apply to him--and the rule is costly, so why do it?
5. But if he thinks either method might be the one that works, penalizing him either way
helps to deter him. When he decides whether to try to commit murder, he must take into
account the risk that he will choose an impossible method and not only will fail, but
might be caught and punished.
D. Of course, another way of providing the same additional deterrence might be by
raising the punishment for success. But what if raising the penalty on methods that
do work is not an option--we can't hang him twice. We can hang him once if he
succeeds, and lock him up if he fails--even by an impossible method.
E. Consider that there is a sense in which any method that fails is "impossible."
1. You can't kill someone by shooting a bullet that misses him (or at least are unlikely to-
-he might get a heart attack).
2. If the world is deterministic, then every attempt had, if only we knew enough, either a
certainty of success or no possibility of success. We are back with the question of
whether to punish attempts.
F. My article on Payne v Tennessee discusses the ex post, ex ante issue in a
somewhat different context.
1. Should murderers be punished more severely (for example, execution instead of life
imprisonment) for killing particularly valuable victims--for example, a mother with
young children?
2. If the answer is "yes," that is a form of ex post punishment--punishment by the
damage actually done.
3. The alternative is to punish according to what the court thinks the murderer knew
when he committed the murder--a sort of ex ante punishment.
4. In other words, punishing you particularly severely if the court thinks you knew the
victim was likely to be a particularly valuable one, but independent of whether the
victim actually was particularly valuable (you get the death penalty for killing someone
in the process of committing suicide, because the court believes that you didn't notice the
empty bottle of sleeping pills next to her).
5. If criminals were risk neutral, and optimal punishment proportional to damage done,
then punishing by damage done works perfectly, since it gives the right <P>.
6. As in ex post/ex ante and impossible crimes context, this assumes that you either do
not have superior knowledge or cannot convery the fact of your superior knowledge to
the criminal. He can only use his knowledge, and you want to give him an incentive to
use it correctly.
7. The article (not the part assigned) also discusses some questions about the relation
between punishment and moral desert which are outside the subject matter of this course
but which some of you may find interesting.
IV. Insurance: A way of thinking through issues of risk and cost allocation.
A. Risk aversion implies gains from transferring, spreading risks.
B. Moral hazard seems to imply a loss from transferring risks.
1. More precisely, it implies a loss from transferring risks away from the person in the
best position to use the incentive from bearing costs to prevent them from happening.
2. But that is not necessarily the person the risk would fall on if we did nothing (didn't
buy insurance, didn't have a legal rule making someone else liable, etc.)
3. So "moral hazard" is sometimes a feature, not a bug--when we shift the risk from the
person it directly falls on (the consumer injured by an exploding coke bottle, the
corporation whose factory burns down) to someone better able to control it (the
producer, the insurance company that specializes in keeping factories from burning
down).
C. Adverse selection:
1. when either buyer or seller has information that the other party lacks, and that cannot
be (convincingly) shared, some worthwhile transactions may fail to take place.
2. One solution is to put the risk on the person who knows how great it is, since that way
the knowledge no longer matters to the person who doesn't have it.
D. Litigation cost is an argument for letting costs lie where they fall.
E. Freedom of contract may provide a way of getting the parties to estimate the net
effect of all these considerations, and draw up the rules accordingly--as we usually
do in the case of insurance.
VII. Property rules (allocation by consent of the owner) vs liability rules (allocation by
someone else taking, owner suing for damages). Why each makes sense for some
problems.
I: What is property?
A. we take the institution for granted--for familiar things
B. But it is a specific kind of rule and concept, as you can see by applying it in less
familiar contexts. My obligations to you are good only against me, but your
ownership of property is good against the world--everybody is legally obliged to
respect it.
C. You ask a friend to borrow his bicycle. Implicit is:
1. he can have it back when he wants
2. If you give it to someone else, the owner can still claim it.
D. You ask a friend for information on a good dentist.
1. He has no right to have it back--to have you stop using the dentist unless you pay him
for the information. Or even to demand that you give him the dentist's name if he
forgets.
2. He has no right against third parties.
E. A gives you a business idea; you sign a non-disclosure agreement, etc. You tell it
to B who tells it to C, who uses it. A can sue you, but he has no claim against C to
"have his idea back," assuming C did not induce the breach.
F. There is a very partial exception to this in trade secret law, discussed below.
G. And a partial exception to the idea that you can always reclaim your property in
the legal rule of "adverse possession," which implies that if someone else treats your
land, or some right with regard to your land (such as the right to walk across it) as
his for long enough (about seven years, varying by state) and you do nothing to
indicate that it is yours, it becomes his.
H. So a recording system becomes important for maintaining property rights,
especially for valuable items such as land.
I. And how fancy the property rights are--to what degree you are free to unbundle
them and sell only part of the bundle--may depend on how easy it is for innocent
third parties to figure out what they are getting. If you unbundle the tires from a car,
the purchaser can learn it by inspection. But what if you unbundle mineral rights
from the land? The right to decide what color your front door is from a house?
J. So for most forms of property other than land, the bundle of rights is fixed.
1. You can sell me your car, along with an agreement that I will not drive it on Sunday or
sell it to anyone who will.
2. But if I resell without requiring the buyer to sign such a contract, you have no claim
against the new owner--he got the full bundle of rights to the car
3. only a claim against me for violating the contract.
V. The Economics
A. Why have protection?
1. Traditional answer: Incentive to produce writings and inventions.
a. But is it the right incentive?
b. The more people will pay to license your patent or buy your books, the greater
the value you have produced, and the greater the reward you get, hence the
incentive.
c. The longer it will be before someone else would have produced the same
intellectual property independently, the greater the value you have produced. And
Copyright accordingly gives longer protection than patent.
d. But patent is still a "one size fits all" system--it is not likely that all patented
inventions would have been independently reinvented in exactly 17 years.
2. To discourage secrecy
a. A patent make secrecy unnecessary, since if someone copies your idea you can
sue him.
b. Giving up secrecy is the price of getting a patent, since you must reveal the best
method of practicing the invention that you know in sufficient detail to allow
others to use it.
3. Kitch homesteading alternative--the objective is to propertize ideas.
a. Once a range of ideas has been converted into private property by a patent, the
owner can develop it, coordinating future research
b. just as a prospector who has filed a claim can develop the mine without
worrying about other people digging holes next to his and taking "his" ore out.
B. Why not use contract instead of intellectual property?
1. The originator of a work or invention could transfer it to others on condition that they
agree not to make copies or use the idea, and only to transfer it to other people who
accept the same agreement.
a. Instead of suing someone for violating your patent or copyright you sue him for
violating his contract with you.
b. But when you find copies being sold, how do you know which of the people
who bought it from you andsigned the contract is the source of the original that is
being copied?
2. Copyright: The problem is how to enforce it against innocent 3rd parties.
a. It could be done by a legal system in which the buyer has only bought part of
the bundle of rights corresponding to the work. He does not have the right to make
copies, so cannot sell it to others. In effect, copyright law creates such a system,
with respect to removing that one item from the bundle.
b. This is the way our legal system handles restrictions on real property, such as
easements and restrictive covenants that "run with the land."
c. But extending it to other forms of property, without the elaborate registration
systems we have for land, could be a problem, and is something our legal system
is generally reluctant to do.
3. Patent.
a. Using contract instead of patent is done to a considerable extent to protect trade
secrets. The rule on innocent 3rd parties who get a trade secret through someone
else's violation of his obligation, without knowing they are doing so, is that they
can practice the secret only if not doing so would impose serious costs on them
(i.e. if they have already built the factory using the secret process).
b. But there is a serious problem with this approach in situations where use and
sale of the patented good, or the good produced by the patented method, reveal the
invention. It is hard to enforce a contract binding every buyer to hide the good he
bought from everyone who will not agree to respect the inventor's sole right in the
ideas it embodies.
3. The issue of contract as a substitute for intellectual property may become an issue
again in the context of computer networks, where new technology may make the
enforcement of intellectual property law very difficult.
4. One solution for copyright would be to somehow tag every copy of the computer
program you sell, so that if a pirate copy appears you can prove which buyer is
responsible--and sue him for violating his agreement not to allow others to copy the
program.
C. Why do we have different patent and copyright rules, and why are they applied to
the things they are applied to?
1. The Constitution refers to "writings and discoveries" but does not specify the rules for
each.
2. Commons problem:
a. Small for copyright--if I didn't write and copyright the book, it is very unlikely
that someone else would have written it.
b. Big for ideas--quite often, several people are trying to make the same invention.
c. So we have much tighter rules and shorter protection for patents than for
copyrights.
3. Costs of fighting over fuzzy boundaries are an argument against protection.
a. Literal copying is easy to spot and prove.
b. Copying of ideas is much harder.
c. So we have easier and longer protection for copyright.
D. Copyright Protection for software.
1. A program is not a writing, since it is intended to control a machine, not be read by a
person (more like a cam--some courts got that right).
2. But it has the characteristics that make copyright suitable to writings.
3. As long as protection is limited to literal copying.
4. A lot of problems appear when you push it to cover non-literal copying.
E. Patent protection for software.
1. The Supreme Court opposed it under the "mental steps doctrine," (you could not
patent something that was simply a series of mental steps, such as the rule for doing long
division) but ...
2. Gradually backed down, under pressure from the CAFC, which was an inferior court
but knew more about the subject and had stronger opinions on it.
3. Many believe creating a problem
4. Not because software is not an invention, but because its characteristics may make
protection cost more than it is worth.
a. A new field, so courts don't understand it very well and give patents for things
already in the art.
b. Very fast changing.
c. Arguably the cost of writing programs is low compared to the cost of making
machines, the sort of thing patent law was designed for, so the incentive of patent
may be unnecessary. Lots of programs were written and lots of progress made
before the Supreme Court started recognizing software patents.
F. Why doesn't patent law pre-empt trade secret law?
1. Sears vs Steiffen says it sometimes does--a state cannot give the equivalent of patent
protection to things that do not qualify for a federal patent.
2. But in general it does not. Kewanee v Bicron says that states are allowed to have trade
secret law, even though it deals with some of the same things as federal patent law, and
does so in a different way.
3. Trade secret helps fill in some of the gaps left by patent law, since ...
a. Patent is one-size-fits-all; either you get it or you don't.
b. You can use trade secret law to protect secrets that are not sufficiently important or
non-obvious or whatever to qualify for patent protection but are still worth something.
c. You can use trade secret to protect secrets too important for patent--ones that you
believe you can keep secret much longer than 17 years (the formula for Coca-Cola, for
example).
d. You can use trade secret to protect ideas that you think are non-obvious but the patent
examiner thinks are obvious. If he is right, someone else will invent the idea, making
your secret worthless. If you are right, you get some of the protection you deserve.
e. And trade secret law has the right incentive pattern with regard to timing--it is not
worth spending a fortune to invent something this year that will be easy to invent next
year, since your trade secret will only last a year.
VI. Coase Article: Classic article that laymen, or at least econ majors, can read.
A. The problem associated with an externality is jointly caused--the result of actions
by both parties.
B. Farmer and cattleman, outcome does not depend on who is liable
1. But bargaining, attempted extortion, etc., is possible
2. So Coase's result holds when everything has been bargained through
3. i.e. in a zero transaction cost world.
C. A bunch more cases with the same logic:
1. Confectioner/doctor
2. Bleaching coconut matting
3. Blocking the draft of a chimney. Who "caused" the nuisance? Both. so
4. Each should bear the full cost--and will under either rule with bargaining.
5. Jolly Anglers brewing. Confined channel of air is presumptively property, by rule of
lost grant belonged to the brewer. So the verdict is the opposite from that in the chimney
case--which also involved blocking an (unconfined) channel of air.
D. Judge's grounds for deciding the cases seem irrelevant to economist, but ...
1. Perhaps all that matters is a predictable rule, (to reduce uncertainty and rent seeking)
and the judges have one, or ...
2. Perhaps the rule is a proxy for relevant considerations, such as
3. Coming to the nuisance.
a. I have a pig farm; the city expands towards it.
b. When you build a housing development next to me, can you enjoin my pig farm
as a nuisance, or ...
c. Can I win by arguing that you "came to the nuisance?"
d. The economic argument is the assymetry of sunk costs: It is cheaper for you to
"move" your housing development before you build it by building it somewhere
else than for me to move my pig farm, which is already there.
e. So the doctrine of coming to the nuisance, which sounds like a moral argument,
may make sense as an economic one.
f. In fact, in modern American law, courts mostly reject the doctrine. Should they?
Not clear.
E. A firm is one solution to the transaction costs of the market
1. Consider a shopping mall.
a. The owner provides free parking, and makes his money back in store rentals.
b. He figures out what mix of stores, restaurants, etc. will make people want to
come, and so maximize the total return
c. He keeps the public areas clean
d. In fact, he provides a centralized alternative to nuisance law, government, etc.
2. Whether it makes more sense to solve problems by putting both actors into one firm
depends on the tradeoff between administrative costs of the firm and the alternative
market costs.
F. Government regulation is another solution
1. Which has costs, and errors, and so may give worse results than the other solutions
2. Or better.
G. And a final solution is to do nothing. Some problems cost more to cure than the
cure is worth.
1. That is how we deal with lots of externalities
2. Positive ones like beautiful buildings, and
3. Negative ones like people wearing ugly clothes.
H. Where transaction costs are high, court decisions matter, and cases suggest at
least some general recognition of reciprocal problem and cost/benefit issues.
I. Common law of nuisance v statute.
1. Statute may extend or reduce the coverage of the law of nuisance.
2. What we observe is frequently government authorised, not the result of lack of
regulation
3. And perhaps should be.
J. Pigou
1. State action is needed; what additional state action?
2. But Pigou's railroad example is due to state action, and ...
3. Not necessarily undesirable. Double causation with use of land.
K. What is owned is a right, not a thing. For instance, the right to produce pollution.
IV. If we do want to enforce the contract, how do you fill in the details?
A. By what would be efficient, either
1. Because we want efficient law, or
2. Because that predicts what they would have agreed to, or
3. Because if you don't they have to waste resources specifying their contract in more
detail so as to avoid your imposition of the terms you want and they don't.
B. Who should bear risks? We've been here before
1. The party who can best risk spread.
2. The party who can best control the risk: moral hazard.
a. Himalayan photographer. If he doesn't tell the photo labs that his six rolls of
film cost thirty thousand dollars to get, they don't owe him thirty thousand when
they lose the film.
b. Risk of strike, factory burning down, is best controlled by the producer--who
owns the factory and negotiates with the workers, but ...
c. Risk of buyer deciding he doesn't need the product is best controlled by the
buyer.
3. The party who best knows the risk--adverse selection.
4. Note that this is relevant both to negotiating the contract and to filling in the details.
C. What happens if someone breaches the contract?
1. Objective. Efficient breach--breach if and only if it makes the parties on net better off.
+ efficiency on other margins which will show up shortly.
2. Nothing: no enforceable contract. Inefficient breach? Not if Coase Theorem applies.
3. Breach forbidden--specific performance. Inefficient performance. Not if ... .
4. Expectation damages:
a. Give the right incentive to breach.
b. The wrong incentive to rely.
c. the wrong incentive to sign if there is asymmetric information
5. Reliance damages:
a. Wrong incentive to breach.
b. Wrong incentive to rely.
c. Right incentive to sign if breaching party has the asymmetric information.
6. Liquidated damages--agree in advance on what the damages will be if a breach
occurs.
a. Right incentive to rely--because damages don't depend on reliance expenditures.
b. Right incentive to breach if and only if the amount agreed on is what
expectation damages would be.
c. Right incentive to sign if and only if the amount agreed on is what reliance
damages would be.
d. Penalty clause--liquidated damage equivalent of specific performance.
7. Property/liability issue:
a. Specific performance or penalty clause is like a property rule--you need the
other party's permission to breach the contract.
b. Expectation or reliance damages are like a liability rule
D. Fraud: Laidlaw v Organ
1. What happened:
a. Purchaser of tobacco knew the war (of 1812)was over; nobody else did.
b. Before to tobacco was delivered the news broke, seller tried to reneg on the deal
c. The court didn't let him.
2. The benefits of the court's position: The ability of people who have advance
information to make money by it, for instance by buying tobacco at wartime prices when
the war is (just barely) over, gives them an incentive to generate such information, and
their use of it puts that information into market prices--the contract bids up the price of
tobacco, as would the news.
3. Why isn't it prevented here by contract? Why doesn't the seller specify that the
contract is void if the buyer has special information?
E. Consider the more general case of speculation.
1. Speculation produces a social benefit by reallocating resources from times when they
are plentiful to times when (an expert can predict that) they will be scarce--the
successful speculator buys low and sells high.
2. By buying grain before other people anticipate the coming shortage he drives up the
price early, giving other people an incentive to use less grain (slaughter hogs early, for
example, to save their feed for human consumption), produce more food of other sorts,
etc.
3. So when the shortage hits and the speculator puts the grain he bought back on the
market, the famine is less severe and the price does not go up as high as if he had not
intervened.
F. This only works if the speculator has secure property rights.
1. If, when the famine happens, a mob seizes his barn full of grain, or the government
confiscates it, speculation won't pay and won't happen.
2. And when there are bad harvests, people will starve
3. Which suggests that the belief that speculators cause famine may be one of the most
lethal errors in human history.
4. It is a result of applying a useful rule of thumb in an inappropriate context.
a. The rule is "cui bono"--to find out who is responsible for something happening,
first figure out who benefits by it.
b. It doesn't work in the case of production, since producers benefit by high prices
but the act of producing increases supply and so makes prices lower than they
would otherwise have been.
G. The successful speculator produces a benefit and gets a reward, but the latter is
not equal, or even closely related to, the former. The relation between the private
value of his activity and the social value of his activity is correct qualitatively (if he
makes money he is also doing good) but not quantitatively (he might do a little good
and make a lot of money, or vice versa).
1. Even in a case where elasticities are low, so that the speculator produces only a small
reallocation and a small benefit, he might still get a large profit--since his speculation
means that resources belong to him instead of to someone else at the instant when their
price goes up.
2. So we might get inefficient speculation--spending $1000 dollars to get information
whose private value is $1100 but whose social value is only $100.
3. aka rent seeking.
VI. Why does it exist: The reason for long term contracting.
A. Sunk costs in the marriage relation.
B. Problems in monitoring and enforcing compliance.
C. No Divorce as one solution
1. Have to live with each other, might as well figure out how.
2. Incentive for more careful search.
3. But note that in real world cases, "no divorce" meant "no remarriage"--separation was
still an option.
D. Easy divorce as another, but ...
1. Cohen's problem, so only if you can get the damage rule right will it lead to only
efficient divorce, but ...
2. That is hard to do, because how do you know who really breached?
3. And what about effects on children?
III. The economics of wedding rings-argument from an article by Margaret Brinig (not
in the packet):
A. Fact: diamond engagement rings became common only starting in the 30's,
peaked in 50's, declined since.
B. Men preferred wives who had never slept with anyone else.
C. Men and women like sex.
D. This creates a problem for those not yet married:
1. For woman, who knows that sex lowers her value on the marriage market
2. For men, who can't find women willing to sleep with them, because ...
E. Solution?
1. Each generation believes it invented sex, despite the evidence, but previous
generations managed somehow.
2. Part of the solution is sex after engagement but before marriage.
3. Which creates a problem of opportunistic breach. Seduce and abandon.
F. One way of controlling this used to be the legal action for breach of promise of
marriage. The victim could collect damages, in large part for her reduced marital
opportunities.
G. Between 1935-1945 the action was abolished in U.S. states containing half the
U.S. population; it has now entirely vanished.
H.The custom of the male giving a valuable engagement ring, which the woman
could keep if he walked out on her, arose--arguably to solve this problem. Think of
it as a performance bond.
I. More recently, the custom has declined--along with the importance of virginity on
the marriage market.
IV. Adoption market:
A. Currently, it is illegal for the adoptive parents to pay the natural mother for her
consent to the adoption. It is legal to pay the lawyers who arrange the adoption, the
mother's medical costs, etc. One consequence seems to be high transaction costs (as
potential adopters bid via lawyers), and a market that shifts between surplus and
shortage.
B. One argument against payments by adopting parents to the natural mother in
exchange for her giving up her child to them for adoption is that the rich will be
buying and the poor selling.
1. This is surely a serious oversimplification; most buyers will be (most Americans are)
neither rich nor poor.
2. In any case, what is wrong with that? Would they ban the markets for housecleaning
and child care on the same grounds?
3. Is it better for the (richer, on average) adoptive parents to get the child from the
(poorer, on average) biological mother, and not pay her--which is what happens now?
C. A more interesting argument, although not one that convinces me:
Commodification
1. How we act and observe other people acting affects how we think. If we treat
something as a commodity, we and others will think of it as a commodity, which might
have bad consequences.
a. If babies can be openly bought and sold, perhaps we will think of them more as
possessions and less as people.
b. If sex can be openly bought and sold (legalized prostitution) perhaps men will
think of women more as sex objects and less as people.
c. So perhaps this is an argument for banning certain acts, not because the acts are
bad, but because they teach a bad lesson--"commodify" things that ought not to be
thought of as commodities.
2. But this argument has an odd feature, constitutionally speaking.
a. We have an act which is both an act and speech.
b. As an act it ought to be permissable (transaction with prostitute or baby seller)
c. We ban it because we disapprove of it as speech
d. Which seems to violate the first amendment.
3. As one student pointed out, a similar argument would seem to apply to laws that
impose special penalties for "hate crimes." If you punish a crime more because, in
addition to doing injury, it also conveys the message "group X are bad people who
should be hated," isn't the additional punishment a punishment for speech? After all, you
couldn't punish someone (in the U.S.) for a speech or a book arguing that "group X are
bad people who should be hated."
V. It is often claimed that, when I have a child, I impose net costs on others, so that
leaving people free to decide how many children they have will result in
overpopulation.
A. But it is not clear what the sign of the net externalities from my having another
child is. Positive externalities include:
1. My child may find the cure for cancer and
2. Will reduce the amount of the national debt your child must bear
3. And the amount your child must pay for national defense, or scientific research, or any
other government service whose costs is roughly independent of the population.
B. This argument is one example of an error common in political discussions in
many areas. You calculate net externalities considering only the externalities of one
sign (negative if you want to ban something, positive if you want to subsidize it) and
ignoring those of the other sign.
C. How in principle do we define the optimal level of population?
1. If we measure it by per capita income, utility, or something similar, we commit a
fallacy of composition.
a. Consider one additional person, who will impose neither net costs nor benefits
on the rest of us. How can we say that his life (utility 10) is a good thing if the rest
of us have an average utility of 9, but the same life is a bad thing of the rest of us
have an average utility of 11?
b. Mead's example: Consider a world with two communities, A and B. Both are
attractive places filled with happy people, but A is a little happier than B. Is the
world a better place if B is wiped out by a plague? Average happiness goes up.
2. If we measure it by total utility, we need to define a zero point, so as to know if an
individual contributes positive or negative utility to the total.
a. The obvious zero point is death, but ...
b. That leads to a rule very favorable to large populations.
c. Two unhappy people are better than one happy one unless they would be willing
to flip a coin: heads they get to be the happy one, tails they die. They will have to
be pretty unhappy to agree to that.
VII. Regulation of Sex. Why do we do it? Adultery laws, fornication laws, ...
I. Tort Law:
A. What it is: a private action for a wrong, typically for damages, although
injunctions are also possible.
B. Differs from criminal law in being a private rather than a state action.
C. And from contract law in not being based on any contract between the parties.
D. Four issues arise:
1. What makes it wrongful: Competition is not a tort. Some system of rights is assumed,
and a tort involves a violation.
2. Causation: What does it mean to say A caused the harm?
3. Liability--strict liability, negligence, contributory negligence, etc.
4. Damages--how calculated?
E. One can think of all these issues in terms of economic efficiency, although
whether doing so describes how the law actually works is an open question.
II. "Wrongful"
A. Tort damages are a version of a Pigouvian tax, so ...
1. We want to treat as wrongful only acts that impost a net externality.
2.And are worth the trouble of dealing with through the legal system.
a. We can use injunctions or punitive damages to enforce a property rule, where it
is the injured party who owns the property.
b. Where the injuring party owns the property and is using it within his rights, we
solve the problem by a transaction--the other party buys the property, or the right.
3. And can be dealt with better in this fashion than by a property rule.
B. Should competition be a tort?
1. When I become the 101st physician in San Jose, the wages of the first 100 physicians
fall--should they be able to sue me?
2. No, because their loss is their patients' gain.
3. So I have imposed only a pecuniary externality--a transfer between two other people,
not a net injury to other people.
IV. Liability
A. Optimal supply of accidents: The accidents we would get if everyone took all and
only cost-justified precautions.
B. Strict liability gives you the right answer with unicausal accidents.
C. Negligence applied to unicausal accidents.
1. Negligence is defined (by economists, but not necessarily by legal scholars) by the
Hand formula (named after Judge Learned Hand, who applied it in a famous case) (T.J.
Hooper)
a. Hand says that you are negligent if you failed to take a precaution whose cost
was less than the expected benefit in accident reduction, in other words ...
b. If you failed to take all cost justified precautions.
2. The rule "you are liable if negligent" gives the right answer if everything is observed
by the court,since:
a. Either you take all cost justified precautions and are not liable, or ...
b. You don't take all cost justified precautions and are liable, and since you are
liable you bear the full cost of the accident, and since you bear the full cost of the
accident it is in your interest to take all cost justified precautions.
c. So you do take all cost justified precautions, which is the outcome we want, but
...
2. What if the efficiency of some classes of precautions is observable by the actor but not
the court?
a. The usual example is "activity level." The court may be able to observe how
many trips you take, but not how much it is worth to you to take them.
b. Another example would be how much attention I pay to my driving.
c. Under a negligence rule, you take the optimal level of the observable
precautions, you will therefore not be found negligence, you therefore ignore costs
to other parties in choosing the level of the unobservable precautions.
3. Negligence could lead to either more or less litigation cost than strict liability.
a. More because there is one more question to be settled (negligence)
b. More because there are more accidents, due to the problem of activity level and
unobservable precautions
c. Less because accidents where the party responsible was obviously not negligent
do not result in lawsuits--the plaintiff has no claim.
Care by
No Yes Yes Yes
Tank
Tank Act No Yes No Yes
Level
Care by Car Yes No Yes Yes
Car Act Yes No Yes No
Level
C. Why are there accidents? In general, because our assumption that both courts and
individuals have perfect information is not true.
1. The court might be wrong about either what precautions the tortfeasor took or what
precautions he should have taken, and so find him negligent when he was not.
2. The tortfeasor might be wrong about what precautions he should have taken, and so
really be negligent. Or ...
3. The tortfeasor might gamble on the court thinking he wasn't negligent when he really
was--and lose.
D. The "reasonable man" standard.
1. One form that imperfect information by the courts takes is the rule that negligence is
judged according to what precautions would be cost effective for an imaginary
"reasonable man" rather than for the actual tortfeasor, since the court doesn't know
whether the tortfeasor has better or worse reactions, higher or lower alcohol tolerance,
etc. than the average.
2. Suppose you have much better reflexes than the average:
a. One half of the argument for keeping down to what the court considers a safe
speed is that if you don't, you will be liable for damages if you run into someone.
That argument still applies to you.
b. The other half is that if you are liable, it is then in your interest to take all cost-
justified precautions. But keeping down to what the court considers a safe speed is
not cost-justified for you.
c. So you either keep down to the court's speed, in order to make sure that if there
is an accident you won't have to pay for it, or
d. Drive at the efficient speed, which is faster than the court things, knowing that
you will be liable if there is an accident.
3. Prediction: Courts should (if Posner is right about the efficiency of the law) tend to
use strict liability where actors vary a lot, such that the "reasonable man" standard works
badly for many of them.
4. More generally, strict liability not just where activity level is important (Posner's
argument), but more generally where unobserved variables are important.
E. Effects of court error depend on the form of the error:
1. Suppose the court correctly measures your precautions but sometimes overestimates
or underestimates the efficient level of precautions. The higher the level of precautions
you take, the greater your chance of not being found negligent, hence liable. This tends
to push you to a greater than optimal level of precautions.
2. Suppose the court simply makes mistakes at random--a third of the time it decides that
the tortfeasor was not negligent, whether or not he actually was. The result is like a strict
liability rule, with a punishment equal (on average) to 2/3 of the damage done. So
tortfeasors are underdeterred, and take less than the efficient level of precaution.
3. So it is hard to work out a theory that takes account of court error--the effect depends
on the details of what sort of mistakes the court makes.
XI. Why pay tort damages to the victim instead of as fines to the state?
A. So he will sue. Private enforcement system
1. But he could threaten to sue in order to be paid by the offender to drop charges.
2. This may be what actually happened in 18th century (and earlier) English criminal
law, where prosecution was private but punishment was by the state.
3. But it works better if the victim owns the case--smaller bargaining range.
4. We could give the right to sue and collect to anyone--but the victim is the one most
likely to know that the tort has happened, and he has the additional incentive of
deterrence.
B. To affect the incentives of the victim?
1. That is a good reason in the strategic case with one tortfeasor who, if damages go to
the state instead of the victims, can get the many victims to take precautions if he refuses
to. This is one way of controlling strategic torts.
2. But just the opposite is true in the non-strategic case (auto accidents). Paying the
damages to the victims reduces their incentive to take precautions to below the optimal
level.
3. Note the difference between an anonymous tort (auto accident, many small players)
and a named tort (deliberate trespass, conversion). where the tortfeasor knows exactly
who the potential victim is, and can bargain with him.
a. Named tort introduces strategic problems, but also ...
b. Possibility of Coase Theorem bargaining
c. Moving us towards a property rule instead of a tort rule.
XII. The problem of measuring and compensating damages for loss of earning
capacity, death, injury.
A. Lump sum vs periodic payments
1. A lump sum reduces disincentive effect, but
2. By the same token lowers the cost of fraud. Once the money is paid you get a ticket to
Lourdes and come back without your crutches.
B. Triple effect of injury
1. On income (readily dealt with)
2. On utility (compensate with cash)
3. On Marginal Utility of Income. This makes compensating for the loss of utility
difficult, expensive, inefficient, perhaps impossible.
4. And explains why the price of a life seems infinite if you try to buy one. It is not that
the value of life is infinite but that the value of money to a corpse is zero.
C. Full compensation vs optimal insurance vs optimal deterrence.
1. Suppose it takes $100 million to make up to you for loss of your sight.
2. You would not insure yourself for that amount.
3. You would not take the precautions, in a case where your actions may risk your sight,
that are implied by that price.
4. So full compensation over insures and over deters.
5. But what if you would not insure at all (death for someone with no dependants)? Does
it follow that the optimal deterrence price is zero? Obviously not.
6. So these are three different values.
D. Correct solution in principle:
1. Set damages at a level that makes people as well off ex ante with the risk as without,
as judged by risk premia for jobs and similar criteria.
2. Allow the sale of inchoate tort claims. Now if my tort claim leaves me "overinsured" I
can sell part of it, so as to consume some of the money now when I am not
dead/blind/whatever.
E. My article which discusses this at much greater length is on the web, linked to the
class page.
XV. Rich vs Poor--should they pay the same fines? In some cases yes, but in others no,
because:
A. For crimes with a payoff in time or utility, the supply curves are different--it
takes a higher expected $ punishment to deter the richer offender.
B. It is cheaper to punish richer offenders, since they can pay fines, but ...
C. On the other hand, they can also hire good lawyers so as to make it costly to
convict them.
D. So the optimal penalty for the rich might be higher or lower than for the poor.
II. Coase Article: Explains the bicausal problem, the "all alternatives imperfect"
problem, argues that the common law courts got things about right.